• Volonté de Dieu et don de la Sagesse
    Nouvelle Revue Théologique 93 (2): 145-166. 1971.
  • La prière d'Azarias
    Nouvelle Revue Théologique 96 (6): 561-582. 1974.
  • Collin, F.-Social Reality
    Philosophical Books 40 72-73. 1999.
  •  20
    Life in Groups: How We Think, Feel, and Act Together comprises thirteen essays by the author relating to human life in groups, together with a substantial introduction and concluding discussion. The essays continue the development and application of the author’s perspective on collective beliefs, emotions, and actions, arguing that these and other central social phenomena are grounded in a joint commitment of the parties. This commitment unifies them, guides their actions going forward, and dete…Read more
  •  38
    Rights and Demands: A Foundational Inquiry
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
    Margaret Gilbert presents the first full-length treatment of a central class of rights: demand-rights. To have such a right is to have the standing or authority to demand a particular action of another person. Gilbert argues that joint commitment is a ground of demand-rights, and gives joint commitment accounts of both agreements and promises.
  •  2
    On Social Facts
    Ethics 102 (4): 853-856. 1989.
  • The Mark of the Social: Discovery or Invention? (edited book)
    with Kenneth J. Gergen, H. S. Gordon, Rom Harrè, Tim Ingold, Raymond I. M. Lee, Peter Manicas, Joseph Margolis, Lloyd Sandelands, Paul F. Secord, Jonathan H. Turner, and Walter L. Wallace
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 1996.
    Behavior, language, development, identity, and science—all of these phenomena are commonly characterized as 'social' in nature. But what does it mean to be 'social'? Is there any intrinsic 'mark' of the social shared by these phenomena? In the first book to shed light on this foundational question, twelve distinguished philosophers and social scientists from several disciplines debate the mark of the social. Their varied answers will be of interest to sociologists, anthropologists, philosophers,…Read more
  •  30
    Plurale Subjekte: Ein Simmelscher Ansatz
    Zeitschrift für Kulturphilosophie 2015 (1-2): 121-142. 2015.
    This paper discusses certain desiderata for an acceptable »Simmelian« account of social groups, and explains why my own account of social groups as plural subjects is preferable to the accounts considered. With regard to the »we«-intentionality of plural subjects, this theory of social groups should be taken to demand only that some rough general type of shared action or shared cognition must be understood to be in question of all sides. It is hoped, then, that this theory of plural subjects in …Read more
  •  21
    Scanlon on Promissory Obligation
    Journal of Philosophy 101 (2): 83-109. 2004.
  •  108
    Sociality, Unity, Objectivity
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 11 153-160. 2001.
    Numerous social and political theorists have referred to social groups or societies as “unities.” What makes a unity of a social group? I address this question with special reference to the theory of social groups proposed in my books On Social Facts and Living Together: Rationality, Sociality and Obligation. I argue that social groups of a central kind require an underlying “joint commitment.” I explain what I mean by a “joint commitment” with care. If joint commitments in my sense underlie the…Read more
  •  24
    Collective Action
    In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Wiley‐blackwell. 2010.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Introduction Observations on Collective Action Approaches to Collective Action The Personal Intentions Approach The ‘We ‐ Intentions’ Approach The Joint Commitment Approach Concluding Remarks Further reading.
  •  112
    New books (review)
    with Anthony Manser, Roger Trigg, R. F. Atkinson, Gerhard Zecha, Edgar Morscher, and C. J. F. Williams
    Mind 80 (320): 623-639. 1971.
  • New books (review)
    Mind 80 (320): 626-629. 1971.
  •  312
    This article offers a critique of Thomas Scanlon's well-known account of promissory obligation by reference to the rights of promisees. Scanlon's account invokes a moral principle, the "principle of fidelity". Now, corresponding to a promisor's obligation to perform is a promisee's right to performance. It is argued that one cannot account for this right in terms of Scanlon's principle. This is so in spite of a clause in the principle relating to the promisee's "consent", which might have been t…Read more
  •  96
    Rationality and salience
    Philosophical Studies 57 (1): 61-77. 1989.
    A number of authors, Including Thomas Schelling and David Lewis, have envisaged a model of the generation of action in coordination problems in which salience plays a crucial role. Empirical studies suggest that human subjects are likely to try for the salient combination of actions, a tendency leading to fortunate results. Does rationality dictate that one aim at the salient combination? Some have thought so, Thus proclaiming that salience is all that is needed to resolve coordination problems …Read more
  •  73
    Rationality and Coordination
    Philosophical Review 105 (1): 105. 1996.
    How is one to act so as to do as well as possible according to one’s ranking of the possible outcomes? How—as it may be put—is one to act rationally? Sometimes the possible outcomes are not under one’s own control: an outcome is a combination of one’s own and another agent’s action. Often, then, one must try to work out what the other agent will do, in order to do as well as possible in one’s own lights. It is situations of this sort—situations of “strategic interaction”—that most concern the ga…Read more
  •  37
    Practical Reasoning in a Social World: How We Act Together
    Philosophical Review 113 (1): 130-132. 2004.
    How does the fact that we are social creatures affect the normative reasons we have for acting? This is the most general question Keith Graham addresses in this wide-ranging book. A normative reason for acting, as Graham understands it, is a consideration about agents or their circumstances, which ought to incline them in the direction of acting in a particular way.
  •  81
    Two claims common in wittgenstein exegesis are addressed, With special reference to a well-known discussion by Peter Winch. First: the claim that one person's language must be intelligible to another is ambiguous; one interpretation is intuitively plausible; strong, Less plausible versions are ascribed to Wittgenstein. Inattention to the ambiguity noted could facilitate their acceptance. Second: the claim that the necessity for standards of correctness in the use of language has as a direct cons…Read more
  •  12
    On Anthropological Knowledge (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 22 (3): 146-147. 1990.
  •  37
    Is an Agreement an Exchange of Promises?
    Journal of Philosophy 90 (12): 627-649. 1993.
  •  33
    Further Reflections on the Social World
    ProtoSociology 35 257-284. 2018.
    This discussion responds to a collection of papers that relate in one way or another to the author’s work in the philosophy of social phenomena. It focuses on those passages that deal most directly with that work. After making some general points that respond to remarks in several of the papers, it turns to the individual papers. The subjects discussed include coordination, conversation, collective beliefs and emotions, joint commitment, obligations and rights, patriotism, promises, the pronoun …Read more
  •  30
  •  38
    Collective Wrongdoing
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (1): 167-187. 2002.
  •  460
    Collective epistemology
    Episteme 1 (2): 95--107. 2004.
    This paper introduces the author's approach to everyday ascriptions of collective cognitive states as in such statements as we believe he is lying. Collective epistemology deals with these ascriptions attempting to understand them and the phenomena in question.