•  402
    Law is traditionally related to the practice of command and hierarchy. It seems that a legal rule should immediately establish a relation between a superior and an inferior. This hierarchical and authoritharian view might however be challenged once the phenomenology of the rule is considered from the internal point of view, that is, from the stance of those that can be said to “use” rather than to “suffer” the rules themselves. A practice oriented approach could in this way open up a more libera…Read more
  •  312
    Le droit est traditionnellement lié à la pratique du commandement et de la hiérarchie. Il semble qu’une règle juridique établisse une immédiate relation entre une norme supérieure et une norme inférieure. La conception hiérarchique et impérative peut néanmoins être remise en cause dès lors que la phénoménologie de la règle juridique est appréhendée d’un point de vue interne, celui de ceux que l’on peut considérer comme les « utilisateurs » de la règle plutôt que ceux qui la subissent. Une approc…Read more
  •  131
    This article provides an assessment of the merits of recent theories of legal reasoning. After a quick historical aperçu a number of models of legal argumentation are presented and discussed, with an eye to their mutual connection. An initial conclusion is that universalizability and discursivity are the common features of those models. The focal question dealt with, however, is that of the impact of the argumentative paradigms of adjudication on the very concept of law. Here the contention is t…Read more
  •  50
    Legal Pluralism as Evolutionary Achievement of Community Law
    Ratio Juris 12 (2): 182-195. 1999.
    After the Maastricht and Amsterdam Conferences the European Union can no longer be conceived as an intergovernmental arrangement: It is a polity founded on an “overlapping consensus.” Consequently, to reconstruct the relations between national and Community law, legal monism does not work, neither in its statist, nor in its international version: Legal pluralism is needed, not in a sociological‐descriptive sense, but as a normative criterion by which a judge (and a citizen) must refer to many an…Read more
  •  45
    "Degenerate Law." Jurists and Nazism
    Ratio Juris 3 (1): 95-99. 1990.
  •  41
    Institutionalism Old and New
    Ratio Juris 6 (2): 190-201. 1993.
    The author deals with the legal theoretical approach that has been labelled “legal institutionalism.” An old and a new version of this approach are singled out: The old one is identified with the theory defended by the Italian public lawyer Santi Romano in the first half of this century; the second one is seen in the recent work by Ota Weinberger and Neil MacCormick. After a short presentation of Romano's work, his ideas and the development proposed by MacCormick and Weinberger are compared. Sim…Read more
  •  39
    This paper takes the dichotomy between “exclusive” and “inclusive” positivism and applies it by analogy to natural-law theories. With John Finnis, and with Beyleved and Brownsword, we have examples of “exclusive natural-law theory,” on which approach the law is valid only if its content satisfies a normative monological moral theory. The discourse theories of Alexy and Habermas are seen instead as “inclusive natural-law theories,” in which the positive law is a constitutive moment in that it ide…Read more
  •  31
  •  27
    Carl Schmitt and the "Third Reich"
    Ratio Juris 4 (2): 261-264. 1991.
  •  27
    This paper discusses some models purported to legitimise a European supranational legal order. In particular, the author focuses on an application of the so‐called regulatory model to the complex structure of the European Community and the European Union. First of all, he tackles the very concept of legitimacy, contrasting it with both efficacy and efficiency. Secondly, he summarises the most prominent positions in the long‐standing debate on the sources of legitimation for the European Communit…Read more
  •  25
    Human Rights: Existential, Not Metaphysical
    Ratio Juris 31 (2): 183-195. 2018.
    My paper consists of four sections. The first is concerned with the distinction and connection between fundamental and human rights. Here I shall just introduce a few conceptual notions and definitions that are more or less widely used, but that may help us to frame the issue and better focus on the most relevant question of the foundation or justification of human rights. In the second and third sections I will present what I believe to be the four fundamental normative situations that shape ou…Read more
  •  24
    Hannah Arendt and the Concept of Law. Against the Tradition
    Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 99 (3): 400-416. 2013.
    A permanent approach to what law is has been that of interpreting it in terms of repression or reduction of chances or courses of conduct. This approach, however, is not able to render justice to fundamental moments of the legal practice, beginning with constitutional law and its empowering rules. Nonetheless, the mainstream in the philosophy of law and in the legal theory has not at all been worried about this strange inadequacy of imperativism to offer a complete view of legal practice and leg…Read more
  •  24
    The Hierarchical Model and H. L. A. Hart’s Concept of Law
    Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 93 (1): 82-100. 2007.
    Law seems to be irremediadibly connected to the experience of coercion and to a structure of hierarchy. This is so because it has traditionally been defined as a set of authoritative prescriptions, usually commands backed by the menace of a sanction, an evil eventually applied through the use of overwhelming violence. Law has also been related to some kind of structure or system which is intrinsically hierarchical, both in the sense of the hierarchy of people whose conduct is addressed by the la…Read more
  •  22
    Law and Morality: A Modest Assessment
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 2 113-129. 1994.
    There are few problems to which legal philosophers have devoted more attention than the relationship between morality and law, or, said in different terms, between the “good” and the “obligatory”. One might think that all that should and could be said about it has already been uttered or written. Nevertheless philosophy — and legal philosophy is no exception — is just this: rethinking old problems which are in fact always new,1 and for which no definitive solution is given — nor is possible, I w…Read more
  •  17
  •  15
    Carl Schmitt and the “Third Reich”
    Ratio Juris 4 (2): 261-264. 1991.
  •  14
    Volume 11, Issue 1, March 2020, Page 92-100.
  •  14
    Rechte und rechtstheoretische Ansätze
    Rechtstheorie 41 (1): 73-86. 2010.
  •  13
    Populism, the Kingdom of Shadows, and the Challenge to Liberal Democracy
    Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 50 (2): 270-280. 2021.
  •  13
    El Derecho contra sí mismo. Un diálogo con Massimo La Torre
    with Amalia Amaya, Leticia Bonifaz, Jorge Cerdio, and Francisco M. Mora-Sifuentes
    UNIVERSITAS Revista de Filosofía Derecho y Política 34 97-130. 2020.
    La presente contribución recoge el diálogo mantenido entre distintos filósofos del Derecho a propósito de la última obra del Profesor Massimo La Torre “Il diritto contro se stesso. Saggio sul positivismo giuridico e la sua crisi”. Al hilo del trabajo del citado autor, los participantes reflexionan sobre preguntas centrales para la teoría y filosofía del Derecho contemporánea: ¿cuál es la naturaleza del Derecho? ¿es el razonamiento jurídico eminentemente moral? ¿qué lugar debe ocupar la práctica …Read more
  •  12
    Libertà ‘repubblicana'? Tra liberalismo e democrazia
    Società Degli Individui 59 149-162. 2017.
  •  11
    Europe Kidnapped
    Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 48 (1): 3-14. 2019.