•  15
    Revolution and Intervention
    Noûs 54 (1): 233-253. 2019.
    Provided that traditional jus ad bellum principles are fulfilled, military humanitarian intervention to stop large scale violations of human rights (such as genocide, crimes against humanity or war crimes) is widely regarded as morally permissible. In cases of “supreme humanitarian emergency”, not only are the victims morally permitted to rebel, but other states are also permitted to militarily intervene. Things are different if the human rights violations in question fall short of supreme human…Read more
  •  147
    Democratic authority and the duty to fight unjust wars
    Analysis 73 (4): 668-676. 2013.
    Just war theory is dominated by two positions. According to the traditional view, combatants both on the just and the unjust side have an equal right to fight, which is not affected by the justice of the cause pursued by their state. According to a recent revisionist account, only combatants fighting for a just cause have such right. David Estlund has offered a sophisticated account that aims to reconcile these two views by looking at our duty to obey the order of democratic political institutio…Read more
  • Pena
    In Mario Ricciardi, Andrea Rossetti & Vito Velluzzi (eds.), Filosofia del diritto, Carocci Editore. 2015.
  •  1
    Human needs, human rights
    In Rowan Cruft, S. Matthew Liao & Massimo Renzo (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford University Press Uk. 2015.
  • Authority and legitimacy
    with Christoph Kletzer
    In John Tasioulas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law, Cambridge University Press. 2020.
  •  24
    Criminalization: The Political Morality of Criminal Law (edited book)
    with R. A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S. E. Marshall, and Victor Tadros
    Oxford University Press. 2014.
    The fourth volume in the Criminalization series, this volume explores some of the most general principles and theories of criminalization. It includes not only philosophical work, but also historical, legal, and sociological investigations into criminalization, clarifying the state of the discipline today.
  •  436
    State Legitimacy and Self-defence
    Law and Philosophy 30 (5): 575-601. 2011.
    In this paper I outline a theory of legitimacy that grounds the state’s right to rule on a natural duty not to harm others. I argue that by refusing to enter the state, anarchists expose those living next to them to the dangers of the state of nature, thereby posing an unjust threat. Since we have a duty not to pose unjust threats to others, anarchists have a duty to leave the state of nature and enter the state. This duty correlates to a claim-right possessed by those living next to them, who a…Read more
  •  41
    Manipulation and liability to defensive harm
    Philosophical Studies 178 (11): 3483-3501. 2021.
    Philosophers working on the morality of harm have paid surprisingly little attention to the problem of manipulation. The aim of this paper is to remedy this lacuna by exploring how liability to defensive harm is affected by the fact that someone posing an unjust threat has been manipulated into doing so. In addressing this problem, the challenge is to answer the following question: Why should it be the case that being misled into posing an unjust threat by manipulation makes a difference to one’…Read more
  •  712
  •  47
    Political Self-Determination and Wars of National Defense
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 15 (6): 706-730. 2018.
  •  350
    Revolution and Intervention
    Noûs 54 (1). 2020.
    Provided that traditional jus ad bellum principles are fulfilled, military humanitarian intervention to stop large scale violations of human rights (such as genocide, crimes against humanity or war crimes) is widely regarded as morally permissible. In cases of “supreme humanitarian emergency”, not only are the victims morally permitted to rebel, but other states are also permitted to militarily intervene. Things are different if the human rights violations in question fall short of supreme…Read more
  •  4
    Le ragioni dell'etica di Luciana Ceri e Filippo Magni
    Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia. forthcoming.
  •  490
    Political Authority and Unjust Wars
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 99 (2): 336-357. 2018.
    Just war theory is currently dominated by two positions. According to the orthodox view, provided that jus in bello principles are respected, combatants have an equal right to fight, regardless of the justice of the cause pursued by their state. According to “revisionists” whenever combatants lack reasons to believe that the war they are ordered to fight is just, their duty is to disobey. I argue that when members of a legitimate state acting in good faith are ordered to fight, they acquire a pr…Read more
  •  38
    “Law, Liberty and Morality”: Fifty Years On (review)
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (3): 417-418. 2013.
  • L'utilitarismo indiretto di Henry Sidgwick
    Rivista di Filosofia 99 (3): 441-465. 2008.
  •  61
    Introduction: Law and philosophy—moral, legal and political perspectives
    with Bjarke Viskum
    Res Publica 14 (4): 237-239. 2008.
    Introduction: Law and Philosophy—Moral, Legal and Political Perspectives Content Type Journal Article Pages 237-239 DOI 10.1007/s11158-008-9068-9 Authors Massimo Renzo, University of Stirling Department of Philosophy Stirling 4LA FK9 UK Bjarke Viskum, University of Århus Department of Jurisprudence Langelandsgade 110, 3 tv. 8000 Arhus C Denmark Journal Res Publica Online ISSN 1572-8692 Print ISSN 1356-4765 Journal Volume Volume 14 Journal Issue Volume 14, Number 4
  •  35
    Helping the Rebels
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 13 (3). 2018.
    In a pair of recent papers, Allen Buchanan has outlined an ambitious account of the ethics of revolution and its implications for military intervention. Buchanan’s account is bold and yet sophisticated. It is bold in that it advances a number of theses that will no doubt strike the reader as highly controversial; it is sophisticated in that it rests on a nuanced account of how revolutions unfold and the constraints that political self-determination places on intervention. He argues that, despite…Read more
  •  43
    Henry Sidgwick's Indirect Utilitarianism
    Rivista di Filosofia 99 (3): 441-466. 2008.
  •  50
    Human rights and the priority of the moral
    Social Philosophy and Policy 32 (1): 127-148. 2015.
    :The main point of contention between “naturalistic” and “political” theories of human rights concerns the need to invoke the notion of moral human rights in justifying the system of human rights included in the international practice. Political theories argue that we should bypass the question of the justification of moral human rights and start with the question of which norms and principles should be adopted to regulate the practice. Naturalistic theories, by contrast, claim that a convincing…Read more
  •  98
    Fairness, self-deception and political obligation
    Philosophical Studies 169 (3): 467-488. 2014.
    I offer a new account of fair-play obligations for non-excludable benefits received from the state. Firstly, I argue that non-acceptance of these benefits frees recipients of fairness obligations only when a counterfactual condition is met; i.e. when non-acceptance would hold up in the closest possible world in which recipients do not hold motivationally-biased beliefs triggered by a desire to free-ride. Secondly, I argue that because of common mechanisms of self-deception there will be recipien…Read more
  •  139
    Crimes Against Humanity and the Limits of International Criminal Law
    Law and Philosophy 31 (4): 443-476. 2012.
    Crimes against humanity are supposed to have a collective dimension with respect both to their victims and their perpetrators. According to the orthodox view, these crimes can be committed by individuals against individuals, but only in the context of a widespread or systematic attack against the group to which the victims belong. In this paper I offer a new conception of crimes against humanity and a new justification for their international prosecution. This conception has important implicatio…Read more
  •  134
    Associative Responsibilities and Political Obligation
    Philosophical Quarterly 62 (246): 106-127. 2012.
    In this paper I criticise an influential version of associative theory of political obligation and I offer a reformulation of the theory in ‘quasi-voluntarist’ terms. I argue that although unable by itself to solve the problem of political obligation, my quasi-voluntarist associative model can play an important role in solving this problem. Moreover, the model teaches us an important methodological lesson about the way in which we should think about the question of political obligation. Finally,…Read more
  •  116
    A Criticism of the International Harm Principle
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 4 (3): 267-282. 2010.
    According to the received view crimes like torture, rape, enslavement or enforced prostitution are domestic crimes if they are committed as isolated or sporadic events, but become crimes against humanity when they are committed as part of a ‘widespread or systematic attack’ against a civilian population. Only in the latter case can these crimes be prosecuted by the international community. One of the most influential accounts of this idea is Larry May’s International Harm Principle, which …Read more
  •  21
    Introduction: Symposium on Causation in War
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (3): 341-345. 2020.
    This article links to the Symposium on Causation in War by Carolina Sartorio, Helen Beebee and Alex Kaiserman, and Lars Christie.
  •  18
    Introduction: Symposium on Causation in War
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (3): 341-345. 2020.
    This article links to the Symposium on Causation in War by Carolina Sartorio, Helen Beebee and Alex Kaiserman, and Lars Christie.
  •  39
    The Constitution of the Criminal Law (edited book)
    with R. A. Duff, Lindsay Farmer, S. E. Marshall, and Victor Tadros
    Oxford University Press. 2013.
    The third book in the Criminalization series examines the constitutionalization of criminal law. It considers how the criminal law is constituted through the political processes of the state; how the agents of the criminal law can be answerable to it themselves; and finally how the criminal law can be constituted as part of the international order.
  •  147
    In this article I criticize a theory of political obligation recently put forward by Christopher Wellman. Wellman's “samaritan theory” grounds both state legitimacy and political obligation in a natural duty to help people in need when this can be done at no unreasonable cost. I argue that this view is not able to account for some important features of the relation between state and citizens that Wellman himself seems to value. My conclusion is that the samaritan theory can only be accepted if w…Read more