•  6
    Time and Causation
    In Heather Dyke & Adrian Bardon (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, Wiley. 2013.
    One of the central characteristics of the causal relation is that it is asymmetric. This chapter looks at possible relations between the direction of time and the causal asymmetry. It first presents a discussion on a causal theory of the temporal asymmetry that takes the causal asymmetry to be basic. It then examines two kinds of accounts that take asymmetric causal relations to be further reducible. The first kind is a subjectivist account of causation that argues that the fact that we describe…Read more
  •  23
  • Why Physics Can't Explain Everything
    In Alastair Wilson (ed.), Chance and Temporal Asymmetry, Oxford University Press. 2014.
  •  651
    Three Ways in Which Pandemic Models May Perform a Pandemic
    with Philippe Van Basshuysen, Lucie White, and Donal Khosrowi
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 14 (1): 110-127. 2021.
    Models not only represent but may also influence their targets in important ways. While models’ abilities to influence outcomes has been studied in the context of economic models, often under the label ‘performativity’, we argue that this phenomenon also pertains to epidemiological models, such as those used for forecasting the trajectory of the Covid-19 pandemic. After identifying three ways in which a model by the Covid-19 Response Team at Imperial College London may have influenced scientific…Read more
  •  544
    When is Lockdown Justified?
    with Lucie White and Philippe van Basshuysen
    Philosophy of Medicine 3 (1): 1-22. 2022.
    How could the initial, drastic decisions to implement “lockdowns” to control the spread of COVID-19 infections be justifiable, when they were made on the basis of such uncertain evidence? We defend the imposition of lockdowns in some countries by first, and focusing on the UK, looking at the evidence that undergirded the decision, second, arguing that this provided us with sufficient grounds to restrict liberty given the circumstances, and third, defending the use of poorly-empirically-constrain…Read more
  •  487
    On the appropriate and inappropriate uses of probability distributions in climate projections and some alternatives
    with Joel Katzav, Erica L. Thompson, James Risbey, David A. Stainforth, and Seamus Bradley
    Climatic Change 169 (15). 2021.
    When do probability distribution functions (PDFs) about future climate misrepresent uncertainty? How can we recognise when such misrepresentation occurs and thus avoid it in reasoning about or communicating our uncertainty? And when we should not use a PDF, what should we do instead? In this paper we address these three questions. We start by providing a classification of types of uncertainty and using this classification to illustrate when PDFs misrepresent our uncertainty in a way that may adv…Read more
  •  43
    Uncertainties, Values, and Climate Targets
    Philosophy of Science 87 (5): 979-990. 2020.
    Using climate policy debates as a case study, I argue that a certain response to the argument from inductive risk, the hedging defense, runs afoul of a reasonable ethical principle: the no-passing-...
  •  30
    This chapter examines two approaches to climate policy: expected utility calculations and a precautionary approach. The former provides the framework for attempts to calculate the social cost of carbon. The latter approach has provided the guiding principle for the United Nations Conference of Parties from the 1992 Rio Declaration to the Paris Agreement. The chapter argues that the deep uncertainties concerning the climate system and climate damages make the exercise of trying to calculate a wel…Read more
  •  16
    This chapter examines the role of parameterParametercalibrationCalibration in the confirmation and validation of complex computer simulation models. I examine the question to what extent calibration data can confirm or validate the calibrated model, focusing in particular on Bayesian approaches to confirmation. I distinguish several different Bayesian approaches to confirmation and argue that complex simulation models exhibit a predictivist effect: Complex computer simulation models constitute a…Read more
  •  20
    Reassessing the Ritz–Einstein debate on the radiation asymmetry in classical electrodynamics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 55 13-23. 2016.
  •  151
    ‘The Most Sacred Tenet’? Causal Reasoning in Physics
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3): 459-474. 2009.
    According to a view widely held among philosophers of science, the notion of cause has no legitimate role to play in mature theories of physics. In this paper I investigate the role of what physicists themselves identify as causal principles in the derivation of dispersion relations. I argue that this case study constitutes a counterexample to the popular view and that causal principles can function as genuine factual constraints. 1. Introduction2. Causality and Dispersion Relations3. Norton's S…Read more
  • The World According to Maxwell
    with London School of Economics and Political Science
    Lse Centre for Philosophy of Natural & Social Science. 1998.
  •  12
    The Dappled World (review)
    with Eric Winsberg, Karen Merikangas Darling, and Arthur Fine
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (7): 403-408. 2000.
  •  63
    Climate Policy in the Age of Trump
    Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 27 (S2): 87-106. 2017.
    As the record-breaking heat of 2016 continues into 2017, making it likely that 2017 will be the second hottest year on record just behind the El Niño year 2016, and as Arctic heat waves pushing the sea ice extent to record lows are mirrored by large scale sheets of meltwater and even rain in Antarctica—the Trump administration is taking dramatic steps to undo the Obama administration’s climate legacy.In its final years, the Obama administration pursued two principal strategies toward climate pol…Read more
  •  77
    Mechanisms, principles, and Lorentz's cautious realism
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36 (4): 659-679. 2005.
    I show that Albert Einstein’s distinction between principle and constructive theories was predated by Hendrik A. Lorentz’s equivalent distinction between mechanism- and principle-theories. I further argue that Lorentz’s views toward realism similarly prefigure what Arthur Fine identified as Einstein’s ‘‘motivational realism.’’ r 2005 Published by Elsevier Ltd.
  •  230
    In recent work on the foundations of statistical mechanics and the arrow of time, Barry Loewer and David Albert have developed a view that defends both a best system account of laws and a physicalist fundamentalism. I argue that there is a tension between their account of laws, which emphasizes the pragmatic element in assessing the relative strength of different deductive systems, and their reductivism or funda- mentalism. If we take the pragmatic dimension in their account seriously, then the …Read more
  •  46
    Users, Structures, and Representation
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (2): 285-306. 2015.
    This article defends a pragmatic and structuralist account of scientific representation of the kind recently proposed by Bas van Fraassen against criticisms of both the structuralist and the pragmatist plank of the account. I argue that the account appears to have the unacceptable consequence that the domain of a theory is restricted to phenomena for which we actually have constructed a model—a worry arising from the account’s pragmatism, which is exacerbated by its structuralism. Yet, the accou…Read more
  •  135
    No place for causes? Causal skepticism in physics
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (3): 313-336. 2012.
    According to a widespread view, which can be traced back to Russell’s famous attack on the notion of cause, causal notions have no legitimate role to play in how mature physical theories represent the world. In this paper I first critically examine a number of arguments for this view that center on the asymmetry of the causal relation and argue that none of them succeed. I then argue that embedding the dynamical models of a theory into richer causal structures can allow us to decide between mode…Read more
  •  11
    Laws in Physics
    European Review 22. 2014.
    What are laws of nature? During much of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries Newton’s laws of motion were taken to be the paradigm of scientific laws thought to constitute universal and necessary eternal truths. But since the turn of the twentieth century we know that Newton’s laws are not universally valid. Does this mean that their status as laws of physics has changed? Have we discovered that the principles, which were once thought to be laws of nature, are not in fact laws?
  •  258
    Does a Low-Entropy Constraint Prevent Us from Influencing the Past
    In Gerhard Ernst & Andreas Hüttemann (eds.), Time, chance and reduction: philosophical aspects of statistical mechanics, Cambridge University Press. pp. 13--33. 2010.
    David Albert and Barry Loewer have argued that the temporal asymmetry of our concept of causal influence or control is grounded in the statistical mechanical assumption of a low-entropy past. In this paper I critically examine Albert's and Loewer 's accounts
  •  28
    Causality and Dispersion: A Reply to John Norton
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3): 487-495. 2009.
    Classical dispersion relations are derived from a time-asymmetric constraint. I argue that the standard causal interpretation of this constraint plays a scientifically legitimate role in dispersion theory, and hence provides a counterexample to the causal skepticism advanced by John Norton and others. Norton ([2009]) argues that the causal interpretation of the time-asymmetric constraint is an empty honorific and that the constraint can be motivated by purely non-causal considerations. In this p…Read more
  •  99
    Causes, Counterfactuals, and Non-Locality
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (4): 655-672. 2010.
    In order to motivate the thesis that there is no single concept of causation that can do justice to all of our core intuitions concerning that concept, Ned Hall has argued that there is a conflict between a counterfactual criterion of causation and the condition of causal locality. In this paper I critically examine Hall's argument within the context of a more general discussion of the role of locality constraints in a causal conception of the world. I present two strategies that defenders of co…Read more
  •  161
    Principle or constructive relativity
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (3): 176-183. 2011.
    I examine Harvey Brown’s account of relativity as dynamic and constructive theory and Michel Janssen recent criticism of it. By contrasting Einstein’s principle-constructive distinction with a related distinction by Lorentz, I argue that Einstein's distinction presents a false dichotomy. Appealing to Lorentz’s distinction, I argue that there is less of a disagreement between Brown and Janssen than appears initially and, hence, that Brown’s view presents less of a departure from orthodoxy than it…Read more
  •  34
    Mechanisms, principles, and Lorentz's cautious realism
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 36 (4): 659-679. 2002.
  •  67
    Mathias Frisch provides the first sustained philosophical discussion of conceptual problems in classical particle-field theories. Part of the book focuses on the problem of a satisfactory equation of motion for charged particles interacting with electromagnetic fields. As Frisch shows, the standard equation of motion results in a mathematically inconsistent theory, yet there is no fully consistent and conceptually unproblematic alternative theory. Frisch describes in detail how the search for a …Read more
  •  74
    Conceptual problems in classical electrodynamics
    Philosophy of Science 75 (1): 93-105. 2008.
    In Frisch 2004 and 2005 I showed that the standard ways of modeling particle-field interactions in classical electrodynamics, which exclude the interactions of a particle with its own field, results in a formal inconsistency, and I argued that attempts to include the self-field lead to numerous conceptual problems. In this paper I respond to criticism of my account in Belot 2007 and Muller 2007. I concede that this inconsistency in itself is less telling than I suggested earlier but argue that e…Read more
  •  105
    Van Fraassen's dissolution of Putnam's model-theoretic argument
    Philosophy of Science 66 (1): 158-164. 1999.
    Bas van Fraassen has recently argued for a "dissolution" of Hilary Putnam's well-known model-theoretic argument. In this paper I argue that, as it stands, van Fraassen's reply to Putnam is unsuccessful. Nonetheless, it suggests the form a successful response might take
  •  96
    Predictivism and old evidence: a critical look at climate model tuning
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (2): 171-190. 2015.
    Many climate scientists have made claims that may suggest that evidence used in tuning or calibrating a climate model cannot be used to evaluate the model. By contrast, the philosophers Katie Steele and Charlotte Werndl have argued that, at least within the context of Bayesian confirmation theory, tuning is simply an instance of hypothesis testing. In this paper I argue for a weak predictivism and in support of a nuanced reading of climate scientists’ concerns about tuning: there are cases, mode…Read more