•  49
    Psychological Causes in Plato’s Phaedo
    Ancient Philosophy Today 4 (2): 196-216. 2022.
    Nearly all of us would accept that at least some of our thoughts – desires, beliefs, and intentions, for example – can be causally responsible for movements in our bodies. Starting in antiquity, and especially since Descartes, philosophers have deployed this claim as the pivotal premise in an increasingly popular line of argument against dualism. The purpose of this paper is to show that, in the Phaedo, Socrates uses this very same claim as the pivotal premise in a surprisingly powerful two-part…Read more
  •  139
    Can Epicureans Be Friends?
    Ancient Philosophy 24 (2): 407-424. 2004.
  •  26
    Book Review: Plato and Aristotle’s Ethics (review)
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (3): 372-374. 2006.
  • Making the Best of Plato's Protagoras
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 48 61-106. 2015.
  •  1
    Lessons from Euthyphro 10a-11b
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 42 1-38. 2012.
  •  677
    Plato on the Possibility of Hedonic Mistakes
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 35 89-124. 2008.
  •  102
    Plato on the Norms of Speech and Thought
    Phronesis 56 (4): 322-349. 2011.
    Near the beginning of the Cratylus (385e-387d) Plato's Socrates argues, against his friend Hermogenes, that the standards of correctness for our use of names in speech are in no way up to us. Yet this conclusion should strike us, at least initially, as bizarre. After all, how could it not be up to us whether to call our children by the names of our parents, or whether to call dogs “dogs“? My aim in this paper will be to show that, although Plato's argument does not succeed in establishing this a…Read more
  •  270
    Plato's Anti-Hedonism'
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 23 (1): 121-145. 2008.
  •  561
    In the Philebus Plato argues that every rational human being, given the choice, will prefer a life that is moderately thoughtful and moderately pleasant to a life that is utterly thoughtless or utterly pleasureless. This is true, he thinks, even if the thoughtless life at issue is intensely pleasant and the pleasureless life at issue is intensely thoughtful. Evidently Plato wants this argument to show that neither pleasure nor thought, taken by itself, is sufficient to make a life choiceworthy f…Read more
  •  649
    Plato and the Meaning of Pain
    Apeiron 40 (1). 2007.
    Most readers of ancient Greek psychology will agree that the Philebus is where we find Plato’s best attempt to theorize about bodily pain.1 But they will probably also agree that the account he develops there has no real chance of being true, and so should not have much appeal to us today — at least insofar as we are philosophers rather than historians. It’s this second conviction that I want to challenge in what follows. More specifically, I want to argue for two connected claims about the meri…Read more