•  15
    Through a curated selection of essays written over four decades by one of Australia’s leading philosophers, this collection demonstrates the impact of Continental philosophy on philosophical thought in Australia.
  • Remembering
    with C. B. Martin
    In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  • La Caze, Marguerite, The Analytic Imaginary
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (4): 611. 2003.
  • LEYDEN, W. VON - "Remembering" (review)
    Mind 71 (n/a): 277. 1962.
  •  23
    VESEY, G. N. A.: "The embodied mind" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 43 (n/a): 402. 1965.
  •  12
  •  3
    Bonney on saying and disbelieving
    Analysis 27 (6): 184-186. 1967.
  •  13
    Judgment After Arendt
    Routledge. 2007.
    Pt. I. Appearances of thought. 1. Appearances. 2. Thinking. 3. Recall -- Pt. II. Thinking with others. 4. By metaphor. 5. Conversing. 6. Absence -- Pt. III. Willing myths. 7. Being willing. 8. Resolving will. 9. Commandment -- Pt. IV. Judgment. 10. Process and judgment. 11. Working magic. 12. Willing thought.
  •  29
    9 page
  • NEEDLEMAN, J.: "The Heart of Philosophy" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (n/a): 375. 1985.
  •  9
    FRENCH, P. S., et. al., , "Midwest Studies in Philosophy", Vol. IV, Studies in Metaphysics (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (n/a): 222. 1981.
  • DURRANT, R. G. : "Essays in Honour of Gwen Taylor" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (n/a): 188. 1984.
  •  20
    Sting of Reason
    Parrhesia 13 82. 2011.
  •  328
    Thinking from underground
    In Vrasidas Ksaralis Danielle Celermajer Andrew Schaap (ed.), Power, Judgment and Political Evil, Ashgate. pp. 27-38. 2010.
    Arendt is a philosopher despite herself, and this paper uses the resources of her <<The Life of the Mind>> to develop her comparison of thinking as a 'departure' from the world with the fore-doomed attempt by Orpheus to bring from underground into the light of day. The paper investigates how thinking, though we 'lose' it in the speech and writing that makes it public, still can have the delicate power that Arendt attributes to it.
  • LANGE, John: The Cognitivity Paradox (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (n/a): 293. 1972.
  •  63
    Hintikka's conception of epistemic logic
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (2). 1969.
    "hintikka's conception of epistemic logic" is a critical comment on hintikka's defence of his philosophical method ("epistemic logic and the methods of philosophical analysis", "a.J.P." no.1, 1968). There is a discussion of the symbolization and analysis of "a knows that p", "a knows that he knows that p", And the notions of virtual equivalence and virtual implication. The conclusion drawn is that whereas hintikka thought his critics misunderstood his method, In fact they were attacking his empl…Read more
  •  60
    A Note on Saying and Disbelieving
    Analysis 25 (3). 1965.
    It is argued that 'p but I do not believe that p' seems close to a contradiction because if the speaker is correct in all that s/he says then what s/he says is false. Similarly,what is wrong with 'p, but I have no opinion whether p' is that, whether 'p' or 'not-p', if the speaker believes it, s/he cannot be completely correct. The argument assumes that 'I believe that' is not a mere parenthesis as in 'p, I believe', and that to say 'I believe that p' is not only to claim a certain mentality, bu…Read more
  •  35
    Simulacra, Enactment and Feeling
    Philosophy 63 (246). 1988.
    The general context of this writing is that of finding exits both from dualism and from reductive physicalism. Dualism—the attitude of seeing and taking things according to a fixed absolute distinction, with mind as invisible, conscious ‘containing’ the thought, feeling and sensation ‘hidden’ by body. Reductive physicalism—the attempt to grasp and be satisfied with body as left over by dualism's rape of its mentality, dualism's refusal to recognize the distinctiveness of point of view, as requir…Read more
  •  32
    Regresses, reasons and grounds
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (1). 1973.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  24
    In sensible judgement
    Ashgate. 2013.
    Achieving judgment -- In sensible judgment -- Sentencing -- Dissenting -- Making judgments -- Judging as right -- Living on the premises -- Inferring, judging, arguing -- Questioning critique -- Sting of reason -- Critique's mystique -- Enigma absolute -- Moving establishment -- Being nomadic -- Chasing after modernity -- When to forget.
  •  28
    Conceptual connection and causal relation
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 54 (1). 1976.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  39
    What is Popper's problem of an empirical basis?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (3). 1969.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  13
  •  91
    Husserl's Transcendental Subjectivity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1). 1980.
    The article aims to show that there are everyday analogues to husserl's 'transcendental' subjectivity, And that this 'transcendence' can be understood as a limit of these varieties of detachment. Evidence is cited that his 'transcendental ego' is the body itself, In its capacity to transcend its conditions. Within this 'naturalized' interpretation of transcendental subjectivity we can see its practical and philosophical importance to our objectivity. His notion of a 'life-World' is a prophylacti…Read more
  •  14
    Analytical Philosophy
    Philosophical Review 77 (4): 500. 1968.
  •  18
    Stories, Pictures, Arguments
    Philosophy 62 (240). 1987.
    There is a tradition of philosophy—a conception we can easily under-stand as a limit of a tendency of our own thinking—that philosophy consists only of argument. The rest of the vast prepon-derance of words in philosophical texts is simply embroidery. ‘Naturally’, it will be conceded, actual philosophy books contain more or less of verbal pictures, words and phrases whose purpose is to evoke images, and many stories—examples, hard cases for definitions, and 4 anecdotes. These, it will be said, ‘…Read more
  • Subjecting and Objecting
    Philosophy 60 (231): 138-140. 1985.
  • In Sensible Judgment
    Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 16 (1): 203-225. 2012.
    The article focuses on the support to the position of Hannah Arendt that taste and feelings have roles in having sensible judgment. It mentions the pleasure that are derived from judgment such as aesthetic judgment and judging what is right. It states that Arendt argues that judgment should be used to defeat moral epithets.