Notre Dame, Indiana, United States of America
  •  5
    Medical Paternalism Reconsidered
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62 (1): 95-98. 2017.
  •  43
    2000-2001 Spring Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic
    with Erich Reck, Colin McLarty, Rohit Parikh, Larry Moss, Scott Weinstein, Gabriel Uzquiano, Grigori Mints, and Richard Zach
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3): 413-419. 2001.
  • Book reviews (review)
    with Donald Rutherford, E. R. Grosholz, D. M. Clarke, A. D. Irvine, Gerhard Heinzmann, I. Jané, N. C. A. Da Costa, and Larry Hauser
    History and Philosophy of Logic 15 (1): 127-147. 1994.
    Hide Ishiguro, Leibniz’s philosophy of logic and language. 2nd ed. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, 1990. x + 246pp. £27.50/$49.50 ; £10.95/$16.95 Massimo Mugnai, Leibniz’ theory of relations. Stuttgart:Franz Steiner Verlag, 1992. 291 pp. 96 DM W. A. Wallace, Galileo’s logic of discovery and proof The background, content, and use of his appropriated treatises on Aristotle’s posterior analytics. Dordrecht, Boston, and London:Kluwer, 1992. xxiii + 323 pp. £84, $139, DF1240 W. A. Wallace, Gali…Read more
  •  2
    Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics (edited book)
    Routledge. 1992.
    This volume of essays addresses the main problem confronting an epistemology for mathematics; namely, the nature and sources of mathematical justification. Attending to both particular and general issues, the essays, by leading philosophers of mathematics, raise important issues for our current understanding of mathematics. Is mathematical justification a priori or a posteriori? What role, if any, does logic play in mathematical reasoning or inference? And of what epistemological importance is t…Read more
  •  24
    Formalism and Hilbert’s understanding of consistency problems
    Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (5): 529-546. 2021.
    Formalism in the philosophy of mathematics has taken a variety of forms and has been advocated for widely divergent reasons. In Sects. 1 and 2, I briefly introduce the major formalist doctrines of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. These are what I call empirico-semantic formalism, game formalism and instrumental formalism. After describing these views, I note some basic points of similarity and difference between them. In the remainder of the paper, I turn my attention to Hilber…Read more
  • Critical essay on W. P. Newton-Smith's The Rationality of Science (review)
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 37 (146): 364-371. 1983.
  • Rigor, Reproof and Bolzano's Critical Program
    In Pierre Edouard Bour, Manuel Rebuschi & Laurent Rollet (eds.), Construction: A Festschrift for Gerhard Heinzmann, King's College Publications. pp. 171-184. 2010.
  • Discovery, Invention and Realism: Gödel and others on the Reality of Concepts
    In John Polkinghorne (ed.), Mathematics and its Significance, Oxford University Press. pp. 73-96. 2011.
    The general question considered is whether and to what extent there are features of our mathematical knowledge that support a realist attitude towards mathematics. I consider, in particular, reasoning from claims such as that mathematicians believe their reasoning to be part of a process of discovery (and not of mere invention), to the view that mathematical entities exist in some mind-independent way although our minds have epistemic access to them.
  • Dedekind against Intuition: Rigor, Scope and the Motives of his Logicism
    In Carlo Cellucci, Emily Grosholz & Emiliano Ippoliti (eds.), Logic and Knowledge, Cambridge Scholars Publications. pp. 205-221. 2011.
  • Freedom and Consistency
    In Emily Goldblatt, B. Kim & R. Downey (eds.), Proceedings of the 12th Asian Logic Conference, World Scientific. pp. 89-111. 2013.
  •  1
    Completeness and the Ends of Axiomatization
    In Juliette Cara Kennedy (ed.), Interpreting Gödel, Cambridge University Press. pp. 59-77. 2014.
    The type of completeness Whitehead and Russell aimed for in their Principia Mathematica was what I call descriptive completeness. This is completeness with respect to the propositions that have been proved in traditional mathematics. The notion of completeness addressed by Gödel in his famous work of 1930 and 1931 was completeness with respect to the truths expressible in a given language. What are the relative significances of these different conceptions of completeness for traditional mathemat…Read more
  • On the motives for proof theory
    In Heinrich Wansing (ed.), Dag Prawitz on Proofs and Meaning, Springer. 2015.
  •  64
    Ian Hacking. Why Is There Philosophy of Mathematics At All?
    Philosophia Mathematica 25 (3): 407-412. 2017.
    © The Author [2017]. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: [email protected] author makes clear that he does not see this book as a contribution to the philosophy of mathematics as traditionally understood. He takes it instead to be an essay about the philosophy of mathematics, one whose purpose is to explain its existence and to make clear the limited extent to which its current and past forms are properly regarded as philosophi…Read more
  •  24
    Hilbert's Program
    Noûs 26 (4): 513-514. 1992.
  •  171
    Poincaré against the logicians
    Synthese 90 (3). 1992.
    Poincaré was a persistent critic of logicism. Unlike most critics of logicism, however, he did not focus his attention on the basic laws of the logicists or the question of their genuinely logical status. Instead, he directed his remarks against the place accorded to logical inference in the logicist's conception of mathematical proof. Following Leibniz, traditional logicist dogma (and this is explicit in Frege) has held that reasoning or inference is everywhere the same — that there are no prin…Read more
  •  88
    Löb's theorem as a limitation on mechanism
    Minds and Machines 12 (3): 353-381. 2002.
    We argue that Löb's Theorem implies a limitation on mechanism. Specifically, we argue, via an application of a generalized version of Löb's Theorem, that any particular device known by an observer to be mechanical cannot be used as an epistemic authority (of a particular type) by that observer: either the belief-set of such an authority is not mechanizable or, if it is, there is no identifiable formal system of which the observer can know (or truly believe) it to be the theorem-set. This gives, …Read more
  •  13
    Duality has often been described as a means of extending our knowledge with a minimal additional outlay of investigative resources. I attempt to construct a serious argument for this view. Certain major elements of this argument are then considered at length. They’re found to be out of keeping with certain widely held views concerning the nature of axiomatic theories (both in projective geometry and elsewhere). They’re also found to require a special form of consistency requirement.
  •  29
    First published in the most ambitious international philosophy project for a generation; the _Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy_. _Logic from A to Z_ is a unique glossary of terms used in formal logic and the philosophy of mathematics. Over 500 entries include key terms found in the study of: * Logic: Argument, Turing Machine, Variable * Set and model theory: Isomorphism, Function * Computability theory: Algorithm, Turing Machine * Plus a table of logical symbols. Extensively cross-referenced…Read more
  •  53
    The mechanization of reason
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (1). 1995.
    Introduction to a special issue of Philosophia Mathematica on the mechanization of reasoning. Authors include: M. Detlefsen, D. Mundici, S. Shanker, S. Shapiro, W. Sieg and C. Wright.
  •  85
    Poincaré vs. Russell on the rôle of logic in mathematicst
    Philosophia Mathematica 1 (1): 24-49. 1993.
    In the early years of this century, Poincaré and Russell engaged in a debate concerning the nature of mathematical reasoning. Siding with Kant, Poincaré argued that mathematical reasoning is characteristically non-logical in character. Russell urged the contrary view, maintaining that (i) the plausibility originally enjoyed by Kant's view was due primarily to the underdeveloped state of logic in his (i.e., Kant's) time, and that (ii) with the aid of recent developments in logic, it is possible t…Read more
  •  139
    On interpreting Gödel's second theorem
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1). 1979.
    In this paper I have considered various attempts to attribute significance to Gödel's second incompleteness theorem (G2 for short). Two of these attempts (Beth-Cohen and the position maintaining that G2 shows the failure of Hilbert's Program), I have argued, are false. Two others (an argument suggested by Beth, Cohen and ??? and Resnik's Interpretation), I argue, are groundless.
  •  1
    Hilbert's formalism
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 47 (186): 285-304. 1993.
    Various parallels between Kant's critical program and Hilbert's formalistic program for the philosophy of mathematics are considered.
  •  30
    Essay Review
    History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (1): 93-105. 1988.
    S. SHAPIRO (ed.), Intensional Mathematics (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 11 3). Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1985. v + 230 pp. $38.50/100Df