•  1
    Intellectual desire, emotion, and action
    In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Explaining Emotions, Univ of California Pr. pp. 323--38. 1980.
  • Examines arguments that maximization holds for conceptual reasons. Looks at maximizing theory and raises conceptual problems for evaluative maximization––difficulties in ranking mixes, problems with organic wholes, and mathematical versus internal evaluative judgments. As regards the evaluative decisions maximization is concerned with, it is argued that we are guided in our understanding of what is good by what is better. To the extent that the better is prior to the good, maximizations are para…Read more
  • According to Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean, virtue and a good life involve a mean of feeling and action. This chapter focuses on David Pear's claim that the Doctrine is conceptually incoherent. It argues that there are serious difficulties in understanding what it could be for courage and its feelings to be in a mean. Courage involves plural and incommensurable values, victory and danger, and the respective emotions, confidence and fear––it is difficult to see how these can be resolved into a…Read more
  • Philosophers commonly argue that conflicts of values are deeply problematic for ethical theories in so far as they force the theories into impracticality, incompleteness, or irrealism. To be complete, a theory must tell us in every case what must be done. To be practical, it must never tell us to do what is impossible. As conflict seems to involve just these features, some philosophers argue from the fact that avoiding conflict is impossible to the conclusion that ethical theories must either be…Read more
  • Addresses the central claim of maximization that we must do what is best. It is argued that maximization is neither morally nor rationally required. Maximization cannot adequately deal with the ethical concepts of superogation, self‐regard, amusement, and friendship; furthermore, the central claims of moral and rational choice do not involve maximization. Moral and rational appraisal of a choice of action requires evaluating its contribution to a whole, where the whole need not be the best avail…Read more
  •  2
    A dirty hands case is justified, obligatory or permissible, and morally wrong. It is argued that dirty hands are conceptually unproblematic and that they are instances of ordinary evaluative phenomena. Some ordinary cases of moral conflict are like dirty hands in that they are entirely justified, yet regrettable. The analysis shows that such cases involve double counting––the disvalue is counted once and overridden in the act‐guiding evaluation, and counted again later as the object of the moral…Read more
  •  1
    Moral Immorality
    In Plural and conflicting values, Oxford University Press. 1989.
    Considers a cognate issue, which is whether what is immoral can nevertheless be admirable. It is argued that admirable immorality, like dirty hands, does not pose special problems for ethical theories. At the heart of admirable immorality lies a conflict of moral virtues, which is unavoidable and necessitates conflict. Looks at two case studies, the painter Paul Gauguin and Winston Churchill.
  • Plurality and Choice
    In Plural and conflicting values, Oxford University Press. 1989.
    Engages with the thesis that plurality is an obstacle to choice. Tackles the worry that incommensurable values make sound comparisons and judgments impossible. It is argued that plural and incommensurable features are ubiquitous to moral life as well as ordinary practical deliberation. Despite this predicament, we are nevertheless able to make sound judgements and to bring together disparate and incommensurable values in complex wholes.
  • Takes up particular issues of conflict and plurality in Aristotle's ethics and moral psychology. Argues that Aristotle explicitly allows for dirty hands as well as conflicts of values and of desires. This involves discussing issues in Aristotle's treatment of voluntariness, mixed acts, eudaimonia, and pleasure. It is argued that for Aristotle, being a good person does not mean that choices among values can be executed lightly, nor does it ensure that the good never experience lack of eudaimonia,…Read more
  • Examines the proposal that value conflict generally requires plural values, and finds that it is correct, but only about a kind of rational conflict, which is rational conflict restricted to practicable options. The focus is on kinds of conflict and whether monism is apt to handle them. The discussion lays out the intricacies of conflict, and its relation to time, agency, and differential care. It is concluded that only pluralism can allow for the lack and loss involved in rational conflict over…Read more
  • Looks at akrasia, monism, and pluralism. Many deem akrasia conceptually incoherent. Others, notably David Wiggins, argue that coherence is secured in so far as incommensurable values are present. Against these views, it is argued that coherent akrasia is possible, and that it requires the distinction between the cognitive and the affective, and not between comparable and commensurable values. Akrasia extends to monistic theories––a monistic theory, e.g. hedonism, is compatible with akrasia. Akra…Read more
  • Introduction
    In Plural and conflicting values, Oxford University Press. 1989.
  •  86
    Acts, Perfect Duties, and Imperfect Duties
    Review of Metaphysics 20 (3). 1967.
    What I have just said strikes me as not only paradoxical but true. In what follows I shall try to show that it is not all that paradoxical and that it is true. In order to show this, and in order to discuss some important and neglected features of act and duty individuation, I shall contrast the concepts of perfect duty and imperfect duty.
  •  41
    Act and Agent Evaluations
    Review of Metaphysics 27 (1). 1973.
    RECENT STUDIES IN NORMATIVE ETHICS have concentrated on act evaluations, neglecting, almost ignoring, agent evaluations. A partial explanation of this defect is found in two related ones: the neglect of act evaluations other than the obligation notions, and the failure to do justice even to them. In each case, neglecting the "other" concepts is implicated in serious misunderstandings of what is considered—or more accurately, what is over-considered. Take, for example, the view that it is obligat…Read more
  •  39
    Values and Purposes
    Journal of Philosophy 78 (12): 747-765. 1981.
  •  379
    Values and purposes: The limits of teleology and the ends of friendship
    Journal of Philosophy 78 (12): 747-765. 1981.
  •  27
    Softening the wires of human emotion
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3): 445-446. 1982.
  •  155
    Psychic feelings: Their importance and irreducibility
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (1): 5-26. 1983.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  88
    Morally Good Intentions
    The Monist 54 (1): 124-141. 1970.
    In this paper I present an analysis of morally good intentions. My starting point is one version of what can be called The Traditional Analysis
  •  69
    Moral Duties, Institutions, and Natural Facts
    The Monist 54 (4): 602-624. 1970.
  •  33
    Good intentions in greek and modern moral virtue
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 57 (3). 1979.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  1021
  •  7
    The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories
    In Roger Crisp & Michael Slote (eds.), Virtue Ethics, Oxford University Press. 1997.
  •  51
    Self-Other Asymmetries and Virtue TheoryFrom Morality to Virtue (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (3): 689. 1994.
  • Valuing Emotions
    with Elizabeth Hegeman
    Philosophy 73 (284): 308-311. 1996.