• Science and the source of legitimacy in democratic regimes
    In Pierluigi Barrotta & Giovanni Scarafile (eds.), Science and democracy: controversies and conflicts, John Benjamins. 2018.
  •  14
    The Meaning of >Craft< (τέχνη) in Plato's Early Philosophy
    Archiv für Begriffsgeschichte 49 7-30. 2007.
    The aim of craft-analogies in Plato's early dialogues is to put forward a theory of knowledge in which only the content of intentional processes can be known. I will argue that, with this goal in mind, Plato offers an idea of craft that differs from, and is even opposed to the views of his time, as well as to those of our own day, by changing the prevailing definition of craft—from the expertise of means to the expertise of ends. I will address the far-reaching consequences of this shift. Part 1…Read more
  •  250
    review of Hila Naot, Raft on the open sea—mand and the world in Jan Patocka
  •  11
    Genera and species vs. laws of nature two epistemic frameworks and their respective ideal worlds
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 81 6-15. 2020.
    This paper seeks to exhibit and explain, by way of comparison, two ideal kinds of knowledge: knowledge based on classifications according to genera and species, as in Aristotelianism and common sense, and scientific knowledge based on the application of laws of nature. I will proceed by attempting (1) to determine the role that presuppositions play in knowledge in general by means of the distinction between content and form; (2) to describe and explain the main features of both ideal forms of kn…Read more
  •  12
    Bentham's 'two theses' argument
    Manuscrito 27 (2): 405-430. 2004.
    Bentham argues that Nature has placed mankind under the governance of pain and pleasure. They determine what we ought to do, as well as what we shall do. Bentham tries to answer two different questions. The first is whether people are actually looking for pleasure. It is a cognitive question about human nature, formulated at a meta-ethical level. The second is whether people ought to look for pleasure. The question is formulated on the ethical level and Bentham asserts that people ought to look …Read more
  •  49
    Book reviews (review)
    with Timothy Cleveland and Anthony J. Graybosch
    Philosophia 29 (1-4): 437-462. 2002.
  •  261
    The Ontological Argument Reconsidered
    with Asnat Avshalom
    Journal of Philosophical Research 15 279-310. 1990.
    The ontological argument- proposed by St. Anselm and developed by Descartes, Leibniz, Kant, Hegel, and Marx- furnishes a key to understanding the relationship between thought and reality. In this article, we shall focus on Hegel’s attitude towards the ontological argument as set out in his Science of Logic, where it appears as a paradigm of the relationship between thought and reality. It should be remarked, moreover, that our choice of the subject was not random and that it was selected for the…Read more
  •  85
    Relation and object in Plato's approach to knowledge
    Theoria 53 (2-3): 141-159. 1987.
    THE aim of this paper is to explain a paradox in Plato's philosophy. On the one hand, Plato reduces virtue to knowledge; on the other, he rejects the possibility of knowledge or at least has serious doubts that it exists. I shall propose in this paper that the definition of virtue as knowledge is a logical outcome of Plato's denial of the particular aspect of knowledge as cognitive relation. This paper may also be considered as an attempt to resolve the Hintikka‐Santas polemic about whether ther…Read more
  • The misunderstandings of hume's paradox of causation
    Giornale di Metafisica 23 (3): 377-398. 2001.
  •  102
    Praxis and poesis in Aristotle's practical philosophy
    Journal of Value Inquiry 24 (3): 185-198. 1990.
    All the paradoxes in the Engberg-Pedersen interpretation and all the present-day discussions about whether energeia is an activity or a state, are not, in my opinion, the result of a defective reading of Aristotle but, rather, the influence of the prevailing values of our industrial society. These values - held, as it seems, by these commentators - are conspicuously teleological: they prevent us from grasping the qualitative difference between praxis and poesis and between energeia and kinesis. …Read more
  •  49
    Circularity of Thought in Hegel's Logic
    Review of Metaphysics 44 (1). 1990.
    HEGEL says that "when enquiry is made as to the kind of predicate belonging to [a] subject, the act of judgement necessarily implies an underlying concept [Begriff]; but this concept is expressed only by the predicate." According to this, some concept of the subject must precede predication. This circularity can be formulated as follows: If the statement is the "factory" in which concepts are produced, how is it that the concepts precede the statement and are not merely produced within it in the…Read more
  •  59
    In the History of Philosophy, the atomistic physics of Epicurus and of Democritus have been considered as very similar.1 Con trary to the more conventional view, Marx considers this similarity
  •  20
    The mind and its depths
    History of European Ideas 22 (1): 61-62. 1996.
  • Mind and the World. By John McDowell
    The European Legacy 3 117-117. 1998.
  •  17
    Aristotle's Theory of πρᾶξις
    Hermes 114 (2): 163-172. 1986.
  •  12
    The Bounds of Freedom: About the Eastern and Western Approaches to Freedom
    with Anan Erev
    Peter Lang Incorporated, International Academic Publishers. 1995.
    The Straniak Philosophy Prize 1995 awarded by the Hermann and Marianne Straniak Foundation Sarnen/Switzerland This book explores Eastern and Western ideas of freedom and reveals the essential differences, as well as similarities, between Eastern and Western cultural values. Inspired by an ancient Greek myth recounted by Protagoras, the authors suggest that three important values tend to motivate human activity: achieving pleasure, achieving results, and obeying moral law. Then, drawing on intell…Read more
  •  17
    Are human beings antithetical in nature? Is there a radical difference between pleasure, efficiency, and moral good, or is the conflict only imaginary? These have traditionally been considered the central questions of Plato's most vivid dialogue, the Protagoras. Many interpreters have seen this dialogue as a confrontation between the moralist and the relativist . This dichotomy is manifest when Plato and Protagoras discuss theoretical questions concerning either knowledge of facts or knowledge o…Read more
  •  1
  •  166
    Time, Understanding, and Will
    with Daniel Arapu and Jean Burrell
    Diogenes 48 (190): 3-21. 2000.
    In the passage from the Enneads devoted to discussing and defining the nature of time, it is written that first one must experience eternity, which, as everyone knows, is the model and archetype of time. This initial warning, which is especially serious because we trust in its sincerity, appears to wipe out all hope of finding common ground with its author.Jorge Luis Borges, History of EternitySo let us leave the Platonists to wander off down a blind alley. Poor simpletons, they think they will …Read more
  •  185
    The moral intellectualism of Plato’s Socrates
    Bochumer Philosophisches Jahrbuch Fur Antike Und Mittelalter 13 (1): 1-14. 2008.
    Commentators do not take Socrates’ theses in the Hippias Minor seriously. They believe it is an aporetic dialogue and even that Socrates does not mean what he says. Hence they are unable to understand the presuppositions behind Socrates’ two interconnected theses: that those who do wrong and lie voluntarily are better than those who do wrong unintentionally, and that no one does wrong and lies voluntarily. Arguing that liars are better than the unenlightened, Socrates concludes that there are no…Read more