• Epistemology dehumanized
    In Quentin Smith (ed.), Epistemology: new essays, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  •  17
  •  33
    Knowledge of the External World (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 490-492. 1993.
  •  8
    Intuition and Ideality
    Noûs 24 (2): 349-352. 1990.
  •  13
    Ethical and Religious Thought in Analytic Philosophy of Language (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3): 732-735. 2001.
  •  58
    Being Qua Being: A Theory of Identity, Existence, and Predication
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (119): 168. 1980.
    Are there nonexistent things? What is the nature of informative identity statements? Are the notions of essential property and of essence intelligible, and, if so, how are they to be understood? Are individual things material substances or clusters of qualities? Can the account of the unity of a complex entity avoid vicious infinite regresses? These questions have attracted widespread attention among philosophers recently, as evidenced by a proliferation of articles in the leading philosophical …Read more
  •  6
    Our Robust Sense of Reality
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 26 (1): 403-421. 1985.
    Anti-Meinongian philosophers, such as Russell, do not explain what they mean by existence when they deny that there are nonexistent objects — they just sense robustly. I argue that any plausible explanation of what they mean tends to undermine their view and to support the Meinongian view. But why are they so strongly convinced that they are right? I argue that the reason is to be found in the special character of the concept of existence, which has been insufficiently examined by anti-Meinongia…Read more
  •  16
    The Vindication of Absolute Idealism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 768-772. 1988.
  •  32
    Being, Identity, and Truth (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 487-490. 1995.
  •  25
    Ontological Categories: Their Nature and Significance
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (227): 301-303. 2007.
  •  20
    Linguistic Representation
    Noûs 15 (1): 81-84. 1981.
  •  7
    The Philosophy of F. H. Bradley
    Noûs 20 (3): 435-437. 1986.
  •  8
  • Prolegomena to a Theory of Relations
    Dissertation, University of Virginia. 1955.
  •  30
    Realism in Ethics
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 395-412. 1988.
  •  21
    Meaning-as-Use and Meaning-as-Correspondence
    Philosophy 35 (135). 1960.
    The purpose of this article is to examine two major arguments in favour of the philosophical thesis that the meaning of an expression is its use, and not its referent or what it corresponds to. A second philosophical thesis which is closely related to the first is that the study of the ordinary, “actual” uses of certain expressions is not of purely linguistic interest but in fact is a way, probably the only proper way, of solving the problems of traditional philosophy; in the sequel to the prese…Read more
  •  48
    Direct Realism without Materialism
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1): 1-21. 1994.
  •  21
    Identity
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2 (1): 70-89. 1977.
  •  15
    Being Qua Being: A Theory of Identity, Existence, and Predication
    with Craig Knoche
    Philosophical Review 89 (2): 310. 1980.
  • "The Vindication of Absolute Idealism" by T. L. S. Sprigge (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 769. 1988.
  •  62
    The Untruth and the Truth of Skepticism
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 67 (4). 1994.
    The skepticism I propose to discuss concerns the reality of an external world of perceivable material objects. There are three questions our skeptic may ask. The first is nonmodal and nonepistemic: Are some of the objects we perceive real? The second is also nonmodal but epistemic: Do we know, or at least have evidence, that some of the objects we perceive are real? The third is both modal and epistemic: Can we know, or at least have evidence, that some of the objects we perceive are real? By de…Read more
  •  25
    That Simple, Indefinable, Nonnatural Property Good
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (1). 1982.
    AT THE end of the earliest exposition of his emotive theory of ethics, Charles Stevenson acknowledged that the obvious response of many would be: "When we ask 'Is X good?' we don't want mere influence, mere advice.... We want our interests to be guided by... truth, and by nothing else. To substitute for such a truth mere emotive meaning and suggestion is to conceal from us the very object of our search." To this Stevenson replied: "I can only answer that I do not understand. What is this truth t…Read more
  •  13
    Wittgenstein’s distinction in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus between what can be said and what can only be shown provides a welcome alternative to the stark choice between contemporary realism and antirealism.[i] It concerns what he thought was “the cardinal problem of philosophy.” Tough-minded philosophers often ask, “What are those things that can only be shown?” But their question misses the point of the distinction. What can only be shown is not a part of reality. But neither is it unreal.
  •  29
    Universals, Qualities, and Quality-Instances (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 21 (3): 137-138. 1989.
  •  6
    The Demand for Justification in Ethics
    Journal of Philosophical Research 15 1-14. 1990.
    The common belief that the epistemic credentials of ethics are quite questionable, and therefore in need of special justification, is an illusion made possible by the logical gap between reason and belief. This gap manifests itself sometimes even outside ethics. In ethics its manifestations are common, because of the practical nature of ethics. The attempt to cover it up takes the form of exorbitant demands for justification and often leads to espousing noncognitivism.
  •  17
    The Philosophy of Appearances (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 44 (3): 613-614. 1991.
    This book is a translation of the original Hungarian edition published in 1971. It belongs in the tradition of Hegel, Marx, and Lukacs, and would be of interest to those appreciative of that tradition. The book begins with a discussion of the general distinction between appearance and reality. According to the author, the distinction has at most a rudimentary application to nature below the social level, but is crucial for understanding society. So the book is primarily concerned with social app…Read more
  •  30
    The ontology of philosophical analysis
    Noûs 15 (1): 3-13. 1981.