•  368
    Understanding Polarization: Meaning, Measures, and Model Evaluation
    with Aaron Bramson, Daniel J. Singer, William J. Berger, Graham Sack, Steven Fisher, Carissa Flocken, and Bennett Holman
    Philosophy of Science 84 (1): 115-159. 2017.
    Polarization is a topic of intense interest among social scientists, but there is significant disagreement regarding the character of the phenomenon and little understanding of underlying mechanics. A first problem, we argue, is that polarization appears in the literature as not one concept but many. In the first part of the article, we distinguish nine phenomena that may be considered polarization, with suggestions of appropriate measures for each. In the second part of the article, we apply th…Read more
  • The Philosopher's Annual, Volume 23 (edited book)
    Center for the Study of Language and Inf. 2002.
    Each year, _The Philosopher's Annual_ presents the ten best articles published in the field of philosophy during the previous twelve months—with the absence of limits on the articles' sources, subject matter, or modes of treatment making for a very diverse collection of engaging, high-caliber work. This year's volume includes papers by Katalin Balog, Tyler Burge, Cheshire Calhoun, Sally Haslanger, Thomas Hofweber, Philip Kitcher, Charles G. Morgan, Thomas W. Pogge, James Pryor, and Elliott Sober
  •  1
    The Philosopher's Annual, Volume 24 (edited book)
    Center for the Study of Language and Inf. 2003.
    This latest volume of _The Philosopher's Annual_ presents the ten best articles published in the field during 2001. No limitations are placed on the articles' sources, subject matter or mode of treatment, providing for a diverse collection of engaging, high-caliber work that stands as a valuable sample of contemporary philosophy. This year's volume includes papers by Robert Bernasconi, Hans Halvorson, Christopher Hitchcock, Ignacio Jane, Brian Leiter, Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel, Joel Pust, Ali…Read more
  •  20
    Influence theory
    Synthese 201 (6): 1-53. 2023.
    Influence theory is a systematic study of formal models of the communicative influence of one person or group of people on another person or group. In that sense influence theory is an overarching philosophical discipline that includes aspects of decision theory and game theory as sub-disciplines as well as established models of de facto segregation, cultural change, opinion polarization, and epistemic networks. What we offer here is a structured outline of formal results that have been scattere…Read more
  •  370
    Given certain standard assumptions-that particular sentences are meaningful, for example, and do genuinely self-attribute their own falsity-the paradoxes appear to show intriguing patterns of generally unstable semantic behavior. In what follows we want to concentrate on those patterns themselves: the pattern of the Liar, for example, which if assumed either true or false appears to oscillate endlessly between truth and falsehood.
  •  48
    The punctuated equilibrium of scientific change: a Bayesian network model
    with Frank Seidl, Calum McNamara, Isabell N. Astor, and Caroline Diaso
    Synthese 200 (4): 1-25. 2022.
    Our scientific theories, like our cognitive structures in general, consist of propositions linked by evidential, explanatory, probabilistic, and logical connections. Those theoretical webs ‘impinge on the world at their edges,’ subject to a continuing barrage of incoming evidence. Our credences in the various elements of those structures change in response to that continuing barrage of evidence, as do the perceived connections between them. Here we model scientific theories as Bayesian nets, wit…Read more
  •  2
    REVIEWS-The philosophical computer
    with G. Mar, P. St Denis, and Petr Hajek
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (3): 347-348. 2000.
  •  86
    Letters to the Editor
    with John D. Sommer, Ed Casey, Mary C. Rawlinson, Eva Kittay, Michael A. Simon, Clyde Lee Miller, Rita Nolan, Marshall Spector, Don Ihde, Peter Williams, Anthony Weston, Donn Welton, Dick Howard, David A. Dilworth, and Tom Foster Digby 3d
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (5). 1993.
    Letters to the Editor
  •  1
    The Philosopher's Annual (edited book)
    with Kenneth Baynes, Peter Ludlow, and Gary Mar
    Ridgeview. 2000.
    Each year, The Philosopher's Annual presents the ten best articles published in the field of philosophy during the previous twelve months—with the absence of limits on the articles' sources, subject matter, or modes of treatment making for a very diverse collection of engaging, high-caliber work. This year's volume includes papers by Katalin Balog, Tyler Burge, Cheshire Calhoun, Sally Haslanger, Thomas Hofweber, Philip Kitcher, Charles G. Morgan, Thomas W. Pogge, James Pryor, and Elliott Sober.
  • What is a Contradiction?
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction, Clarendon Press. 2004.
  • What is a Contradiction?
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, Clarendon Press. 2006.
  •  491
    We motivate a picture of social epistemology that sees forgetting as subject to epistemic evaluation. Using computer simulations of a simple agent-based model, we show that how agents forget can have as large an impact on group epistemic outcomes as how they share information. But, how we forget, unlike how we form beliefs, isn’t typically taken to be the sort of thing that can be epistemically rational or justified. We consider what we take to be the most promising argument for this claim …Read more
  •  252
    Epistemic justifications for democracy have been offered in terms of two different aspects of decision-making: voting and deliberation, or 'votes' and 'talk.' The Condorcet Jury Theorem is appealed to as a justification in terms of votes, and the Hong-Page "Diversity Trumps Ability" result is appealed to as a justification in terms of deliberation. Both of these, however, are most plausibly construed as models of direct democracy, with full and direct participation across the population. In t…Read more
  •  218
    In a series of formal studies and less formal applications, Hong and Page offer a ‘diversity trumps ability’ result on the basis of a computational experiment accompanied by a mathematical theorem as explanatory background (Hong & Page 2004, 2009; Page 2007, 2011). “[W]e find that a random collection of agents drawn from a large set of limited-ability agents typically outperforms a collection of the very best agents from that same set” (2004, p. 16386). The result has been extremely influential…Read more
  •  299
    Philosophy of Science, Network Theory, and Conceptual Change: Paradigm Shifts as Information Cascades
    with Joshua Kavner, Lloyd Shatkin, and Manjari Trivedi
    In Euel Elliot & L. Douglas Kiel (eds.), Complex Systems in the Social and Behavioral Sciences: Theory, Method, and Application, University of Michigan Press. forthcoming.
    Philosophers have long tried to understand scientific change in terms of a dynamics of revision within ‘theoretical frameworks,’ ‘disciplinary matrices,’ ‘scientific paradigms’ or ‘conceptual schemes.’ No-one, however, has made clear precisely how one might model such a conceptual scheme, nor what form change dynamics within such a structure could be expected to take. In this paper we take some first steps in applying network theory to the issue, modeling conceptual schemes as simple networ…Read more
  •  987
    A Multidisciplinary Understanding of Polarization
    with Jiin Jung, Daniel J. Singer, Aaron Bramson, William J. Berger, Bennett Holman, and Karen Kovaka
    American Psychologist 74 301-314. 2019.
    This article aims to describe the last 10 years of the collaborative scientific endeavors on polarization in particular and collective problem-solving in general by our multidisciplinary research team. We describe the team’s disciplinary composition—social psychology, political science, social philosophy/epistemology, and complex systems science— highlighting the shared and unique skill sets of our group members and how each discipline contributes to studying polarization and collective problem-…Read more
  •  414
    Modeling Epistemology: Examples and Analysis in Computational Philosophy of Science
    In A. Del Barrio, C. J. Lynch, F. J. Barros & X. Hu (eds.), IEEE SpringSim Proceedings 2019, Ieee. pp. 1-12. 2019.
    What structure of scientific communication and cooperation, between what kinds of investigators, is best positioned to lead us to the truth? Against an outline of standard philosophical characteristics and a recent turn to social epistemology, this paper surveys highlights within two strands of computational philosophy of science that attempt to work toward an answer to this question. Both strands emerge from abstract rational choice theory and the analytic tradition in philosophy of science rat…Read more
  •  136
    Free Will in Context
    Behavioral Science and the Law 25 183-201. 2007.
    Philosophical work on free will, contemporary as well as historical, is inevitably framed by the problem of free will and determinism. One of my goals in what follows is to give a feel for the main lines of that debate in philosophy today. I will also be outlining a particular perspective on free will. Many working philosophers consider themselves Compatibilists; the perspective outlined, building on a number of arguments in the recent literature, is a contemporary form of such a view. It canno…Read more
  •  336
    Plantinga's God and Other Monstrosities
    Religious Studies 15 35-41. 1979.
    Variations on the ontological argument for most minimal and most mediocre beings.
  •  339
    Against a Deontic Argument for God's Existence
    Analysis 42 (3): 171-174. 1982.
    Against an argument by Carl Kordig.
  •  191
    Problems for Omniscience
    In J. P. Moreland, Chad Meister & Khaldoun A. Sweis (eds.), Debating Christian Theism, Oxford Univ. Press. pp. 169-180. 2013.
    A survey of logical problems for the concept of omniscience.
  •  306
    What Won't Escape Sorites Arguments
    Analysis 42 (1): 38-43. 1982.
    Problems for 'precise replacements' as a way out of sorites paradoxes.
  •  320
    Self-reference and Chaos in Fuzzy Logic
    IEEE Transactions on Fuzzy Systems 1 237-253. 1993.
    The purpose of this paper is to open for investigation a range of phenomena familiar from dynamical systems or chaos theory which appear in a simple fuzzy logic with the introduction of self-reference. Within that logic, self-referential sentences exhibit properties of fixed point attractors, fixed point repellers, and full chaos on the [0, 1] interval. Strange attractors and fractals appear in two dimensions in the graphing of pairs of mutually referential sentences and appear in three dimens…Read more
  •  154
    Essential Vagueness: Two Models, One Simple Truth
    In Ali Abasenezhad & Otavio Bueno (eds.), On the Sorites, Springer. forthcoming.
    What the Sorites has to tell us is a simple truth regarding our categories. It appears to saddle us with something other than a simple truth—something worse, a contradiction or a problem or a paradox—only when we insist on viewing it through a discrete logic of categories. Discrete categories and discrete logic are for robots. We aren’t robots, and the simple truth is that we don’t handle categories in the way any discrete logic would demand. For us non-robots, what the Sorites has to offer …Read more
  •  396
    The iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma has become the standard model for the evolution of cooperative behavior within a community of egoistic agents, frequently cited for implications in both sociology and biology. Due primarily to the work of Axelrod (1980a, 198Ob, 1984, 1985), a strategy of tit for tat (TFT) has established a reputation as being particularly robust. Nowak and Sigmund (1992) have shown, however, that in a world of stochastic error or imperfect communication, it is not TFT that finall…Read more
  •  230
    Undecidability in the Spatialized Prisoner's Dilemma
    Theory and Decision 42 (1): 53-80. 1997.
    n the spatialized Prisoner’s Dilemma, players compete against their immediate neighbors and adopt a neighbor’s strategy should it prove locally superior. Fields of strategies evolve in the manner of cellular automata (Nowak and May, 1993; Mar and St. Denis, 1993a,b; Grim 1995, 1996). Often a question arises as to what the eventual outcome of an initial spatial configuration of strategies will be: Will a single strategy prove triumphant in the sense of progressively conquering more and more terri…Read more
  •  330
    Learning to Communicate: The Emergence of Signaling in Spatialized Arrays of Neural Nets
    with Trina Kokalis and Paul St Denis
    Adaptive Behavior 10 45-70. 2003.
    We work with a large spatialized array of individuals in an environment of drifting food sources and predators. The behavior of each individual is generated by its simple neural net; individuals are capable of making one of two sounds and are capable of responding to sounds from their immediate neighbors by opening their mouths or hiding. An individual whose mouth is open in the presence of food is “fed” and gains points; an individual who fails to hide when a predator is present is “hurt” by lo…Read more