Washington, District of Columbia, United States of America
  •  2540
    What Is Structuralism?
    Partisan Review 35 (1). 1968.
  •  359
    The paradox of induction and the inductive wager
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22 (4): 512-520. 1962.
  •  358
    Committees and consensus: How many heads are better than one?
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 16 (4): 375-391. 1991.
    The first section of this paper asks why the notion of consensus has recently come to the fore in the medical humanities, and suggests that the answer is a function of growing technological and professional complexity. The next two sections examine the concept of consensus analytically, citing some of the recent philosophical literature. The fourth section looks at committee deliberations and their desirable outcomes, and questions the degree to which consensus serves those outcomes. In the fift…Read more
  •  140
    Mathematics and the Laws of Nature
    Bulletin of the Kansas Association of Teachers of Mathematics 34 (2): 11-12. 1959.
  •  120
    La inducción: una paradoja y una apuesta
    Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Costa Rica 8 329-336. 1960.
  •  83
    Choosing Emotions: The Late Sartre and the Early Flaubert
    Bulletin de la Société Américaine de Philosophie de Langue Française 4 (2-3): 209-217. 1992.
    - none -
  •  71
    What Happened in Paris
    Partisan Review 35 (4): 519-525. 1968.
  •  70
    To hell and back: Sartre on (and in) analysis with Freud
    Sartre Studies International 11 (s 1-2): 166-176. 2005.
    On the back cover of the original French edition of Sartre's Le scénario Freud (The Freud Scenario), the promotional blurb poses the question: "Est-ce ici Sartre qui analyse Freud ou Freud qui analyse Sartre?" (Is Sartre analyzing Freud here, or is Freud analyzing Sartre?). We do not, for obvious reasons, have anything of Freud's on Sartre, but we do have quite a lot of Sartre on Freud, and great quantities of Sartre on Sartre. It has sometimes seemed to me that reading through everything that S…Read more
  •  68
    Communication Lag
    Science Communication 20 (1): 14-21. 1998.
  •  65
    Moral certainty in Tolstoy
    Philosophy and Literature 24 (1): 49-66. 2000.
  •  61
    The functions of definition in science
    Philosophy of Science 26 (3): 201-228. 1959.
    Definition is viewed in this paper as a cohesive element of theory, providing links between scientific constructs. The problem is approached first in terms of three orders--the historical, the logical, and the heuristic--in which the structure of science may be put together; a study of these is necessary if difficulties about priority of definition are to be resolved. The main part of the paper is devoted to an exercise in theory-construction which illustrates the five principal functions of def…Read more
  •  60
  •  57
    The Decline of Conceptual Thinking
    The Centennial Review 1 (4): 419-441. 1957.
  •  56
    Jusqu'au moment de la mort, tout le monde est immortel
    Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 5 (1): 39-45. 1993.
    none.
  •  47
    Reviews (review)
    Synthese 17 (1): 219-253. 1967.
  •  47
    The Fading of the Postmodern
    Bulletin de la Société Américaine de Philosophie de Langue Française 6 (3): 34-42. 1994.
    none
  •  46
    Reviews (review)
    with Michael Martin, Robert L. Causey, Ernest W. Adams, and Peter Achinstein
    Synthese 25 (1-2): 219-253. 1972.
  •  44
    What Sartre wasn't
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (10): 596-597. 1982.
  •  40
    Coherence, System, and Structure
    Idealistic Studies 4 (1): 2-17. 1974.
    Systematic philosophy has for a long time now been disavowed as an objective or even as an interest by many professional philosophers whose view of their subject regards it as an activity of analysis rather than of construction. That this disclaimer should have become so common at a time when, in other disciplines, the idea of system was coming more and more into prominence suggests that philosophers and other scholars may somehow have been talking at cross-purposes. The opposition of analytic a…Read more
  •  39
    Book review section: Science theory and experience (review)
    with Donald Lee
    World Futures 7 (3): 65-78. 1969.
  •  38
    Science, computers, and the complexity of nature
    Philosophy of Science 30 (2): 158-164. 1963.
    The relations between simplicity and economy, and between simplicity and complexity, are briefly discussed, and it is suggested that an appearance of simplicity may arise out of the matching of two complexities, e.g. in the perception of a simple color. Following out this idea, it is shown that scientific activity may be regarded as a matching of theoretical complexity against the complexity of nature, which leads to an expectation of an optimum theoretical complexity for successful scientific w…Read more
  •  36
    Subjectivity in the machine
    Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 18 (September): 291-308. 1988.
  •  34
    Modern Movements in European Philosophy (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (3): 266-268. 1989.