•  22
    Is the set of all self-membered sets, S, a member of itself? In naive set theory, this is Russell’s hypodox. By the Laws of Excluded Middle and Non-contradiction, S is a member of itself xor it is not, but no principle of classical logic or naive set theory determines which. (Herein, ‘xor’ extends English with a specifically exclusive disjunction.) As a hypodox, the Truth-teller is a sentence that says of itself simply that it is true; by the above mentioned principles, the Truth-teller is true …Read more
  •  125
    Squeezing arguments
    Analysis 71 (1): 22-30. 2011.
    Many of our concepts are introduced to us via, and seem only to be constrained by, roughand-ready explanations and some sample paradigm positive and negative applications. This happens even in informal logic and mathematics. Yet in some cases, the concepts in question – although only informally and vaguely characterized – in fact have, or appear to have, entirely determinate extensions. Here’s one familiar example. When we start learning computability theory, we are introduced to the idea of an …Read more
  •  42
    Mathematical Thought and its Objects
    Analysis 69 (3). 2009.
    Needless to say, Charles Parsons’s long awaited book1 is a must-read for anyone with an interest in the philosophy of mathematics. But as Parsons himself says, this has been a very long time in the writing. Its chapters extensively “draw on”, “incorporate material from”, “overlap considerably with”, or “are expanded versions of” papers published over the last twenty-five or so years. What we are reading is thus a multi-layered text with different passages added at different times. And this makes…Read more
  •  144
    Pinocchio beards the Barber
    Analysis 72 (4): 749-752. 2012.
    The Pinocchio paradox poses one dialetheia too many for semantic dialetheists (Eldridge-Smith 2011). However, Beall (2011) thinks that the Pinocchio scenario is merely an impossible story, like that of the village barber who shaves just those villagers who do not shave themselves. Meanwhile, Beall maintains that Liar paradoxes generate dialetheia. The Barber scenario is self-contradictory, yet the Pinocchio scenario requires a principle of truth for a contradiction. In this and other respects th…Read more
  •  19
    Arthur N. Prior on the Labours of Ł3 Conjunctions
    History and Philosophy of Logic 1-7. forthcoming.
    In ‘Many-valued Logics’, a lecture broadcast over New Zealand's public radio in 1957, Arthur N. Prior (1914–1969) complained that conjunctions are put ‘to something like forced labour’ in Łukasiewicz's three-valued semantics, Ł3. In this paper, we discuss what Prior might have meant by this.
  •  44
    In Search of Modal Hypodoxes using Paradox Hypodox Duality
    Philosophia 50 (5): 2457-2476. 2022.
    The concept of hypodox is dual to the concept of paradox. Whereas a paradox is incompatibly overdetermined, a hypodox is underdetermined. Indeed, many particular paradoxes have dual hypodoxes. So, naively the dual of Russell’s Paradox is whether the set of all sets that are members of themselves is self-membered. The dual of the Liar Paradox is the Truth-teller, and a hypodoxical dual of the Heterological paradox is whether ‘autological’ is autological. I provide some analysis of the duality and…Read more
  •  114
    Is 'no' a force-indicator? Sometimes, possibly
    Analysis 72 (2): 225-231. 2012.
    Some bilateralists have suggested that some of our negative answers to yes-or-no questions are cases of rejection. Mark Textor (2011. Is ‘no’ a force-indicator? No! Analysis 71: 448–56) has recently argued that this suggestion falls prey to a version of the Frege-Geach problem. This note reviews Textor's objection and shows why it fails. We conclude with some brief remarks concerning where we think that future attacks on bilateralism should be directed
  •  58
    Two Fallacies in Proofs of the Liar Paradox
    Philosophia 48 (3): 947-966. 2020.
    At some step in proving the Liar Paradox in natural language, a sentence is derived that seems overdetermined with respect to its semantic value. This is complemented by Tarski’s Theorem that a formal language cannot consistently contain a naive truth predicate given the laws of logic used in proving the Liar paradox. I argue that proofs of the Eubulidean Liar either use a principle of truth with non-canonical names in a fallacious way or make a fallacious use of substitution of identicals. Tars…Read more
  •  44
    The Liar Hypodox: A Truth-Teller’s Guide to Defusing Proofs of the Liar Paradox
    Open Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 152-171. 2019.
    It seems that the Truth-teller is either true or false, but there is no accepted principle determining which it is. From this point of view, the Truth-teller is a hypodox. A hypodox is a conundrum like a paradox, but consistent. Sometimes, accepting an additional principle will convert a hypodox into a paradox. Conversely, in some cases, retracting or restricting a principle will convert a paradox to a hypodox. This last point suggests a new method of avoiding inconsistency. This article provide…Read more
  •  409
    Rejection and valuations
    Analysis 70 (1). 2010.
    Timothy Smiley’s wonderful paper ‘Rejection’ (1996) is still perhaps not as well known or well understood as it should be. This note first gives a quick presentation of themes from that paper, though done in our own way, and then considers a putative line of objection – recently advanced by Julien Murzi and Ole Hjortland (2009) – to one of Smiley’s key claims. Along the way, we consider the prospects for an intuitionistic approach to some of the issues discussed in Smiley’s paper.
  •  8
    Our last big theorem – Theorem 6 – tells us that if a theory meets certain conditions, then it must be negation incomplete. And we made some initial arm-waving remarks to the effect that it seems plausible that we should want theories which meet those conditions. Later, we announced that there actually is a consistent weak arithmetic with a first-order logic which meets the conditions (in which case, stronger arithmetics will also meet the conditions); but we didn’t say anything about what such …Read more
  •  52
    In the very last chapter of my Introduction to Gödel Theorems, I rashly claimed that there is a sense in which we can informally prove Church’s Thesis. This sort of claim isn’t novel to me: but it certainly is still very much the minority line. So maybe it is worth rehearsing some of the arguments again. Even if I don’t substantially add to the arguments in the book, it might help to approach things in a different order, with some different emphases, to make the issue as clear as possible.
  •  43
    There is a familiar derivation of G¨ odel’s Theorem from the proof by diagonalization of the unsolvability of the Halting Problem. That proof, though, still involves a kind of self-referential trick, as we in effect construct a sentence that says ‘the algorithm searching for a proof of me doesn’t halt’. It is worth showing, then, that some core results in the theory of partial recursive functions directly entail G¨ odel’s First Incompleteness Theorem without any further self-referential trick.
  •  20
    In Episode 1, we introduced the very idea of a negation-incomplete formalized theory T . We noted that if we aim to construct a theory of basic arithmetic, we’ll ideally like the theory to be able to prove all the truths expressible in the language of basic arithmetic, and hence to be negation complete. But Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem says, very roughly, that a nice theory T containing enough arithmetic will always be negation incomplete. Now, the Theorem comes in two flavours, dependin…Read more
  •  21
    Theorem 1. If T is a sound formalized theory whose language contains the language of basic arithmetic, then there will be a true sentence GT of basic arithmetic such that T GT and ¬GT, so T must be negation incomplete.
  •  50
    In the section ‘Further reading’, I listed a book that arrived on my desk just as I was sending IGT off to the press, namely Church’s Thesis after 70 Years edited by Adam Olszewski et al. On the basis of a quick glance, I warned that the twenty two essays in the book did seem to be of ‘variable quality’. But actually, things turn out to be a bit worse than that: the collection really isn’t very good at all! After I sent my book to press, I gave a paper-by-paper review on my blog, at http://logic…Read more
  •  34
    Pinocchio against the Semantic Hierarchies
    Philosophia 46 (4): 817-830. 2018.
    The Liar paradox is an obstacle to a theory of truth, but a Liar sentence need not contain a semantic predicate. The Pinocchio paradox, devised by Veronique Eldridge-Smith, was the first published paradox to show this. Pinocchio’s nose grows if, and only if, what Pinocchio is saying is untrue. What happens if Pinocchio says that his nose is growing? Eldridge-Smith and Eldridge-Smith : 212-5, 2010) posed the Pinocchio paradox against the Tarskian-Kripkean solutions to the Liar paradox that use la…Read more
  •  64
    Unlike his other major typescripts, the Big Typescript is divided into titled chapters, themselves divided into titled sections. But within a section we still get a collection of remarks typically without connecting tissue and lacking any transparently significant ordering or helpful signposting. So we still encounter the usual difficulties in trying to think our way through into what Wittgenstein might be wanting to say. Some enthusiasts like to try to persuade us that the aphoristic style is r…Read more
  •  72
    We are going to prove a key theorem that tells us just a bit more about the structure of the non-standard countable models of first-order Peano Arithmetic; and then we will very briefly consider whether any broadly philosophical morals can be drawn from the technical result
  •  44
    • How to construct a ‘canonical’ Gödel sentence • If PA is sound, it is negation imcomplete • Generalizing that result to sound p.r. axiomatized theories whose language extends LA • ω-incompleteness, ω-inconsistency • If PA is ω-consistent, it is negation imcomplete • Generalizing that result to ω-consistent p.r. axiomatized theories which extend Q..
  •  42
    Here is Hilbert is his famous address of 1900: The supply of problems in mathematics is inexhaustible, and as soon as one problem is solved numerous others come forth in its place. Permit me in the following, tentatively as it were, to mention particular definite problems, drawn from various branches of mathematics, from the discussion of which an advancement of science may be expected
  •  93
    odel’s Theorems (CUP, heavily corrected fourth printing 2009: henceforth IGT ). Surely that’s more than enough to be going on with? Ah, but there’s the snag. It is more than enough. In the writing, as is the way with these things, the book grew far beyond the scope of the lecture notes from which it started. And while I hope the result is still pretty accessible to someone prepared to put in the time and effort, there is – to be frank – a lot more in the book than is really needed by philosopher…Read more
  •  41
    The first main topic of this paper is a weak second-order theory that sits between firstorder Peano Arithmetic PA1 and axiomatized second-order Peano Arithmetic PA2 – namely, that much-investigated theory known in the trade as ACA0. What I’m going to argue is that ACA0, in its standard form, lacks a cogent conceptual motivation. Now, that claim – when the wraps are off – will turn out to be rather less exciting than it sounds. It isn’t that all the work that has been done on ACA0 has been hopele…Read more
  •  22
    Here’s one version G¨ odel’s 1931 First Incompleteness Theorem: If T is a nice, sound theory of arithmetic, then it is incomplete, i.e. there are arithmetical sentences ϕ such that T proves neither ϕ nor ¬ϕ. There are three things here to explain straight away.
  •  16
    Why these notes? After all, I’ve written An Introduction to Gödel’s Theorems. Surely that’s more than enough to be going on with? Ah, but there’s the snag. It is more than enough. In the writing, as is the way with these things, the book grew far beyond the scope of the lecture notes from which it started. And while I hope the result is still pretty accessible to someone prepared to put in the time and effort, there’s a lot more in the book than is really needed by philosophers meeting the incom…Read more
  •  5
    The last Episode wasn’t about logic or formal theories at all: it was about common-or-garden arithmetic and the informal notion of computability. We noted that addition can be defined in terms of repeated applications of the successor function. Multiplication can be defined in terms of repeated applications of addition. The exponential and factorial functions can be defined, in different ways, in terms of repeated applications of multiplication. There’s already a pattern emerging here! The main …Read more