•  1
    Intuitionism
    with David McNaugton
    In Hugh LaFollette & Ingmar Persson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, Blackwell. pp. 287-310. 2013.
    What makes an action morally obligatory, the one that we are morally required to do? Different moral theories give different answers to this question. The simplest answer would be that just one consideration is relevant to the rightness of an action. Act‐consequentialism (which we will refer to as “consequentialism,” unless otherwise indicated) is a popular and influential theory that claims just this. On this view, the only morally relevant consideration is the effect an action will have on the…Read more
  •  1
    Holism about value
    with D. McNaugton
    In Vojko Strahovnik, Matjaz Potrc & Mark Norris Lance (eds.), Challenging Moral Particularism, Routledge. pp. 166--184. 2008.
  •  4
    Decision Theory and Degree of Belief
    In Stephen P. Turner & Paul A. Roth (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Blackwell. 2003.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern Rational Choice Theory Prescription and Description Ramsey's Theory Dutch Books and the Epistemic Objection Savage's Theory What is Preference and Why is it More Basic than Qualitative Probability? Context Freedom and the Transitivity of Preference The Causal Independence of Acts and Events The Constant Act Problem Allais's and Ellsberg's Examples Conclusion.
  •  6
    Davidson's Measurement‐Theoretic Analogy
    In Ernie Lepore & Kurt Ludwig (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Donald Davidson, Blackwell. 2013.
    Donald Davidson is famous for, among other things, his theory of radical interpretation – an account of how it is that we can attribute meanings to people's words, and contents to their mental states, based on an apparent paucity of evidence. This account is infused with ideas from, and applications of, the general theory of measurement, as well as one specific instance of that theory – decision theory. In addition, however, Davidson also applies measurement theory – in the form of his “measurem…Read more
  •  62
    Radical Interpretation and Logical Pluralism
    Topoi 38 (2): 277-289. 2019.
    I examine Quine’s and Davidson’s arguments to the effect that classical logic is the one and only correct logic. This conclusion is drawn from their views on radical translation and interpretation, respectively. I focus on the latter, but I first address, independently, Quine’s argument to the effect that the ‘deviant’ logician, who departs from classical logic, is merely changing the subject. Regarding logical pluralism, the question is whether there is more than one correct logic. I argue that…Read more
  •  29
    Naturalism And Normativity: Reply to McNaughton and Rawling
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104 (1): 187-203. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling's anti-reductionist intentions are to be welcomed, but are not well served by their continuing adherence to a neo-Humean notion of the 'descriptive'. Their too-willing acceptance of this notion is reflected in a denial of appropriate dialectical weight to considerations about the way 'pattern' disappears from the domain of value when we try to characterize the constituent features of the latter in non-evaluative terms. The need for a satisfactory account of the immanence o…Read more
  •  9
    Book Reviews (review)
    with George Huxley, John J. Ansbro, Maeve Cooke, John Preston, Garin V. Dowd, John Bussanich, Flash Q. Fiasco, José Luis Bermúdez, Lucie A. Antoniol, João Branquinho, Jérôme Dokic, Peter König, Iseult Honohan, and Paul S. Miklowitz
    Humana Mente 3 (2): 346-382. 1995.
  •  172
    Naturalism and Normativity
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1). 2003.
    Simon Blackburn can be seen as challenging those committed to sui generis moral facts to explain the supervenience of the moral on the descriptive. We (like perhaps Derek Parfit) hold that normative facts in general are sui generis. We also hold that the normative supervenes on the descriptive, and we here endeavour to answer the generalization of Blackburn's challenge. In the course of pursuing this answer, we suggest that Frank Jackson's descriptivism rests on a conception of properties inappr…Read more
  • Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    In Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred Dycus Miller & Jeffrey Paul (eds.), Utilitarianism: the aggregation question, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
  •  51
    Blameworthiness and Dependence
    Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1): 110-124. 2023.
    Some recent accounts of blameworthiness present this property as response-dependent: an agent is blameworthy, they say, if and only if, and (if so) in virtue of the fact that, it is fitting to respond to her with a certain blaming emotion. Given the explanatory aim of these views, the selected emotion cannot be said simply to appraise its object as blameworthy. We argue that articulation of the appraisal in other terms suggested by proponents yields a failure of the coextension required by the a…Read more
  •  206
    Reason to Feel Guilty
    In Andreas Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility, Cambridge University Press. pp. 217-36. 2022.
    Let F be a fact in virtue of which an agent, S, is blameworthy for performing an act of A-ing. We advance a slightly qualified version of the following thesis: (Reason) F is (at some time) a reason for S to feel guilty (to some extent) for A-ing. Leaving implicit the qualification concerning extent, we claim as well: (Desert) S's having this reason suffices for S’s deserving to feel guilty for A-ing. We also advance a third thesis connecting desert of feeling guilty with the fitti…Read more
  •  288
    True Blame
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 101 (3): 736-749. 2023.
    1. We sometimes angrily confront, pointedly ostracize, castigate, or denounce those whom we think have committed moral offences. Conduct of this kind may be called blaming behaviour. When genuine,...
  •  15
    Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184): 390-393. 1996.
  •  20
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy (edited book)
    with Philip Wilson
    Routledge. 2018.
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy presents the first comprehensive, state of the art overview of the complex relationship between the field of translation studies and the study of philosophy. The book is divided into four sections covering discussions of canonical philosophers, central themes in translation studies from a philosophical perspective, case studies of how philosophy has been translated and illustrations of new developments. With twenty-nine chapters written by int…Read more
  •  65
    A note on the two envelopes problem
    Theory and Decision 36 (1): 97-102. 1994.
  •  156
    Unprincipled Ethics
    In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral Particularism, Clarendon Press. 1988.
  •  112
    Honoring and promoting values
    Ethics 102 (4): 835-843. 1992.
  •  80
    Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1): 354-374. 2009.
    We reject Moorean holism about value—the view that the value of the whole does not equal the sum of the values of its parts. We propose an alternative aggregative holism according to which the value of a state of affairs is the sum of the values of its constituent states. But these constituents must be evaluated in situ
  •  496
    On defending deontology
    Ratio 11 (1). 1998.
    This paper comprises three sections. First, we offer a traditional defence of deontology, in the manner of, for example, W.D. Ross (1965). The leading idea of such a defence is that the right is independent of the good. Second, we modify the now standard account of the distinction, in terms of the agent-relative/agentneutral divide, between deontology and consequentialism. (This modification is necessary if indirect consequentialism is to count as a form of consequentialism.) Third, we challenge…Read more
  •  45
    The ranking of preference
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161): 495-501. 1990.
  •  140
    Deontology
    with David McNaughton and Florida State University
    In David Copp (ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  132
  •  63
    Perspectives on a Pair of Envelopes
    Theory and Decision 43 (3): 253-277. 1997.
    The two envelopes problem has generated a significant number of publications (I have benefitted from reading many of them, only some of which I cite; see the epilogue for a historical note). Part of my purpose here is to provide a review of previous results (with somewhat simpler demonstrations). In addition, I hope to clear up what I see as some misconceptions concerning the problem. Within a countably additive probability framework, the problem illustrates a breakdown of dominance with respect…Read more
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 14 (2): 342-349. 1998.
  •  113
    Introduction: Aspects of Rationality
    In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    This article examines the nature of rationality. The domain of rationality is customarily divided into the theoretical and the practical. Whereas theoretical or epistemic rationality is concerned with what it is rational to believe, and sometimes with rational degrees of belief, practical rationality is concerned with what it is rational to do, or intend or desire to do. This article raises some of the main issues relevant to philosophical discussion of the nature of rationality. Discussions of …Read more
  •  69