•  1
    Intuitionism
    with David McNaugton
    In Hugh LaFollette & Ingmar Persson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, Blackwell. pp. 287-310. 2013.
    What makes an action morally obligatory, the one that we are morally required to do? Different moral theories give different answers to this question. The simplest answer would be that just one consideration is relevant to the rightness of an action. Act‐consequentialism (which we will refer to as “consequentialism,” unless otherwise indicated) is a popular and influential theory that claims just this. On this view, the only morally relevant consideration is the effect an action will have on the…Read more
  •  1
    Holism about value
    with D. McNaugton
    In Vojko Strahovnik, Matjaz Potrc & Mark Norris Lance (eds.), Challenging Moral Particularism, Routledge. pp. 166--184. 2008.
  •  4
    Decision Theory and Degree of Belief
    In Stephen P. Turner & Paul A. Roth (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Blackwell. 2003.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern Rational Choice Theory Prescription and Description Ramsey's Theory Dutch Books and the Epistemic Objection Savage's Theory What is Preference and Why is it More Basic than Qualitative Probability? Context Freedom and the Transitivity of Preference The Causal Independence of Acts and Events The Constant Act Problem Allais's and Ellsberg's Examples Conclusion.
  •  6
    Davidson's Measurement‐Theoretic Analogy
    In Ernie Lepore & Kurt Ludwig (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Donald Davidson, Blackwell. 2013.
    Donald Davidson is famous for, among other things, his theory of radical interpretation – an account of how it is that we can attribute meanings to people's words, and contents to their mental states, based on an apparent paucity of evidence. This account is infused with ideas from, and applications of, the general theory of measurement, as well as one specific instance of that theory – decision theory. In addition, however, Davidson also applies measurement theory – in the form of his “measurem…Read more
  •  62
    Radical Interpretation and Logical Pluralism
    Topoi 38 (2): 277-289. 2019.
    I examine Quine’s and Davidson’s arguments to the effect that classical logic is the one and only correct logic. This conclusion is drawn from their views on radical translation and interpretation, respectively. I focus on the latter, but I first address, independently, Quine’s argument to the effect that the ‘deviant’ logician, who departs from classical logic, is merely changing the subject. Regarding logical pluralism, the question is whether there is more than one correct logic. I argue that…Read more
  •  29
    Naturalism And Normativity: Reply to McNaughton and Rawling
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104 (1): 187-203. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling's anti-reductionist intentions are to be welcomed, but are not well served by their continuing adherence to a neo-Humean notion of the 'descriptive'. Their too-willing acceptance of this notion is reflected in a denial of appropriate dialectical weight to considerations about the way 'pattern' disappears from the domain of value when we try to characterize the constituent features of the latter in non-evaluative terms. The need for a satisfactory account of the immanence o…Read more
  •  9
    Book Reviews (review)
    with George Huxley, John J. Ansbro, Maeve Cooke, John Preston, Garin V. Dowd, John Bussanich, Flash Q. Fiasco, José Luis Bermúdez, Lucie A. Antoniol, João Branquinho, Jérôme Dokic, Peter König, Iseult Honohan, and Paul S. Miklowitz
    Humana Mente 3 (2): 346-382. 1995.
  •  172
    Naturalism and Normativity
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1). 2003.
    Simon Blackburn can be seen as challenging those committed to sui generis moral facts to explain the supervenience of the moral on the descriptive. We (like perhaps Derek Parfit) hold that normative facts in general are sui generis. We also hold that the normative supervenes on the descriptive, and we here endeavour to answer the generalization of Blackburn's challenge. In the course of pursuing this answer, we suggest that Frank Jackson's descriptivism rests on a conception of properties inappr…Read more
  • Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    In Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred Dycus Miller & Jeffrey Paul (eds.), Utilitarianism: the aggregation question, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
  •  51
    Blameworthiness and Dependence
    Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1): 110-124. 2023.
    Some recent accounts of blameworthiness present this property as response-dependent: an agent is blameworthy, they say, if and only if, and (if so) in virtue of the fact that, it is fitting to respond to her with a certain blaming emotion. Given the explanatory aim of these views, the selected emotion cannot be said simply to appraise its object as blameworthy. We argue that articulation of the appraisal in other terms suggested by proponents yields a failure of the coextension required by the a…Read more
  •  206
    Reason to Feel Guilty
    In Andreas Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility, Cambridge University Press. pp. 217-36. 2022.
    Let F be a fact in virtue of which an agent, S, is blameworthy for performing an act of A-ing. We advance a slightly qualified version of the following thesis: (Reason) F is (at some time) a reason for S to feel guilty (to some extent) for A-ing. Leaving implicit the qualification concerning extent, we claim as well: (Desert) S's having this reason suffices for S’s deserving to feel guilty for A-ing. We also advance a third thesis connecting desert of feeling guilty with the fitti…Read more
  •  291
    True Blame
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 101 (3): 736-749. 2023.
    1. We sometimes angrily confront, pointedly ostracize, castigate, or denounce those whom we think have committed moral offences. Conduct of this kind may be called blaming behaviour. When genuine,...
  •  15
    Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184): 390-393. 1996.
  •  20
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy (edited book)
    with Philip Wilson
    Routledge. 2018.
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy presents the first comprehensive, state of the art overview of the complex relationship between the field of translation studies and the study of philosophy. The book is divided into four sections covering discussions of canonical philosophers, central themes in translation studies from a philosophical perspective, case studies of how philosophy has been translated and illustrations of new developments. With twenty-nine chapters written by int…Read more
  •  144
    Deontology and Agency
    The Monist 76 (1): 81-100. 1993.
    Any adequate account of the distinction between consequentialist and deontological moral systems must take account of the central place given to constraints in the latter. Constraints place limits on what each of us may do in the pursuit of any goal, including the maximisation of the good. There is some debate, however, both over how constraints are to be characterised, and over the rationale for their inclusion in a moral system. Some authors view constraints as agent-relative: a constraint sup…Read more
  •  51
    Expected Utility, Ordering, and Context Freedom
    Economics and Philosophy 13 (1): 79. 1997.
    The context-free weak ordering principle is viewed by many as a cornerstone of rational choice theory. McClennen, for example, claims that this principle is one of a pair on which '[t]he theory of rational choice and preference, as it has been developed in the past few decades by economists and decision theorists, rests', and Sen characterizes a version of context freedom as ‘a very basic requirement of rational choice’. But this principle is certainly not uncontroversial: there are examples of …Read more
  • The Logical Status of Conditionalization and its Role in Confirmation Commentary
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 71 77-94. 2000.
  • Psychology and Newtonian Methodology
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 16 (1): 35-43. 1995.
    According to Newton, the goals of natural philosophy comprise quantitative generalizations and causal knowledge, the latter being paramount. Quantitative generalizations are sometimes explanatory, in psychology as elsewhere . However, in psychology, they are not explanatory when the human subject is considered qua bearer of psychological states , but only when she is considered qua physical system. In the former case quantitative generalizations are, rather, to be causally explained. In this sen…Read more
  •  211
    Value and Agent-Relative Reasons
    Utilitas 7 (1): 31. 1995.
    In recent years the distinction between agent-relative and agent-neutral reasons has been taken by many to play a key role in distinguishing deontology from consequentialism. It is central to all universalist consequentialist theories that value is determined impersonally; the real value of any state of affairs does not depend on the point of view of the agent. No reference, therefore, to the agent or to his or her position in the world need enter into a consequentialist understanding of what ma…Read more
  •  65
    A note on the two envelopes problem
    Theory and Decision 36 (1): 97-102. 1994.
  •  156
    Unprincipled Ethics
    In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral particularism, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  •  112
    Honoring and promoting values
    Ethics 102 (4): 835-843. 1992.
  •  80
    Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1): 354-374. 2009.
    We reject Moorean holism about value—the view that the value of the whole does not equal the sum of the values of its parts. We propose an alternative aggregative holism according to which the value of a state of affairs is the sum of the values of its constituent states. But these constituents must be evaluated in situ