•  232
    Duns Scotus and Analogy
    Modern Schoolman 89 (3-4): 147-154. 2012.
    Duns Scotus defends the view that we can speak univocally of God and creatures. When we do so, we use words in the same sense in the two cases. Scotus maintains that the concepts that these univocal words signify are themselves univocal: the same concept in the two cases. In this paper, I consider a related question: does Duns Scotus have the notion of analogous concepts—concepts whose relation to each other lies somewhere between the univocal and the equivocal? Using some neglected texts from S…Read more
  •  171
    Recent work on the philosophy of duns scotus
    Philosophy Compass 5 (8): 667-675. 2010.
    This article highlights five areas of Scotus' philosophy that have recently been the subject of scholarly discussion. (1) Metaphysics : I outline the most current accounts of Scotus on individuation (thisness or haecceity) and the common nature. (2) Modal theory : I consider recent accounts both of Scotus' innovations in spelling out the notion of the logically (and broadly logically) possible, and of his account of the independence of modality. (3) Cognitive psychology : I examine recent views …Read more
  •  170
  •  143
    Atonement without satisfaction
    Religious Studies 37 (4): 397-416. 2001.
    According to Swinburne, one way of dealing with the guilt that attaches to a morally bad action is satisfaction, consisting of repentance, apology, reparation, and penance. Thus, Christ's life and death make atonement for human sin by providing a reparation which human beings would otherwise be unable to pay. I argue that the nature of God's creative activity entails that human beings can by themselves make reparation for their sins, merely by apology. So there is no need for additional reparati…Read more
  •  143
    Anti-Pelagianism and the Resistibility of Grace
    Faith and Philosophy 22 (2): 199-210. 2005.
  •  133
    Two models of the trinity?
    Heythrop Journal 43 (3). 2002.
    Contrary to a common assumption, I argue that there is full agreement between East and West on the issue of the relation between the divine essence and the divine persons. I defend this claim by using the understanding of universals found in D. M. Armstrong to cast light on the theories. Taking Gregory of Nyssa and John of Damascus as representatives of the Eastern tradition, I show that this tradition sees the divine essence as a numerically singular object that is wholly present in each divine…Read more
  •  133
    Four-dimensionalism and identity across time: Henry of ghent vs. Bonaventure
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (3): 393-414. 1999.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Four-Dimensionalism and Identity Across Time: Henry of Ghent vs. BonaventureRichard CrossModern accounts of the identity of an object across time tend to fall roughly into two basic types.Let us say that something persists ıff, somehow or other, it exists at various times; this is the neutral word. Something perdures iff it persists by having different temporal parts, or stages, at different times, though no one part of it is wholly …Read more
  •  132
    Ockham on part and whole
    Vivarium 37 (2): 143-167. 1999.
  •  130
    According to Scotus, an intelligible species with universal content, inherent in the mind, is a partial cause of an occurrent cognition whose immediate object is the self-same species. I attempt to explain how Scotus defends the possibility of this causal activity. Scotus claims, generally, that forms are causes, and that inherence makes no difference to the capacity of a form to cause an effect. He illustrates this by examining a case in which an accident is an instrument of a substance in the …Read more
  •  124
    Duns Scotus on Eternity and Timelessness
    Faith and Philosophy 14 (1): 3-25. 1997.
    Scotus consistently holds that eternity is to be understood as timelessness. In his early Lectura, he criticizes Aquinas’ account of eternity on the grounds that (1) it entails collapsing past and future into the present, and (2) it entails a B-theory of time, according to which past, present and future are all ontologically on a par with each other. Scotus later comes to accept something like Aquinas’ account of God’s timelessness and the B-theory of time which it entails. Scotus also offers a …Read more
  •  122
    The Incarnation
    In Thomas P. Flint & Michael Rea (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophical theology, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The Christian doctrine of the Incarnation maintains that the second person of the Trinity became a human being, retaining all attributes necessary for being divine and gaining all attributes necessary for being human. As usually understood, the doctrine involves the claim that the second person of the Trinity is the subject of the attributes of Jesus Christ, the first-century Jew whose deeds are reported in various ways in the New Testament. The fundamental philosophical problem specific to the …Read more
  •  118
    Duns scotus: Some recent research
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (3): 271-295. 2011.
    Duns Scotus (c. 1266-1308) has long ranked as one of the most challenging of philosophers. He was known from shortly after his death as doctor subtilis—the subtle doctor—and his obscure style and complex thought-processes make him a hard thinker to study. That said, he quickly established an almost cult following among his students, and his thought, for all its density, remained hugely popular throughout the Middle Ages and beyond. It is no exaggeration to claim that the last two decades have se…Read more
  •  118
  •  109
    According to an important set of medieval arguments, it is impossible to make a distinction between creation and conservation on the assumption of a beginningless universe. The argument is that, on such an assumption, either God is never causally sufficient for the existence of the universe, or, if He is at one time causally sufficient for the existence of the universe, He is at all times causally sufficient for the universe, and occasionalism is true. I defend the claim that these arguments are…Read more
  •  103
    Book Review: Love of Self and Love of God in Thirteenth-Century Ethics (review)
    Studies in Christian Ethics 20 (1): 146-150. 2007.
  •  98
    Henry of ghent on the reality of non-existing possibles – revisited
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92 (2): 115-132. 2010.
    According to a well-known interpretation, Henry of Ghent holds that possible but non-existent essences – items merely with what Henry labels ‘ esse essentiae ’ – have some reality external to the divine mind, but short of actual existence ( esse existentiae ). I argue that this reading of Henry is mistaken. Furthermore, Henry identifies any essence, considered independently of its existence as a universal concept or as instantiated in a particular as an item that has some kind of reality in the …Read more
  •  87
    Incarnation, omnipresence, and action at a distance
    Neue Zeitschrift für Systematicsche Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 45 (3): 293-312. 2003.
  •  83
    I—Marilyn McCord Adams: What's Metaphysically Special about Supposits? Some Medieval Variations on Aristotelian Substance 1
    with Marilyn McCord Adams
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1): 15-52. 2005.
  •  82
    Duns Scotus
    Oxford University Press. 1999.
    The nature and content of the thought of Duns Scotus (c. 1266-1308) remains largely unknown except by the expert. This book provides an accessible account of Scotus' theology, focusing both on what is distinctive in his thought, and on issues where his insights might prove to be of perennial value.
  •  81
    According to Henry of Ghent (d. 1293), it is impossible for the second person of the Trinity to assume into unity of person an irrational nature (e.g., a stone nature), or to assume a rational nature that does not enjoy the beatific vision. He argues that the assumption of a nature to a divine person entails both that the nature has the sort of powers that could exercise supernatural activities and that these powers are exercised. Henry’s Franciscan opponents argue against this. Existent irratio…Read more
  •  81
    Is Aquinas's proof for the indestructibility of the soul successful?
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 5 (1). 1997.
    No abstract
  •  75
    Infinity, Continuity, and Composition: The Contribution of Gregory of Rimini
    Medieval Philosophy & Theology 7 (1): 89-110. 1998.
    Gregory of Rimini (1300s motivations for accepting this view, and indeed how precisely he understands it
  •  73
    Form and Universal in Boethius
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (3): 439-458. 2012.
    Contrary to the claims of recent commentators, I argue that Boethius holds a modified version of the Ammonian three-fold universal (transcendent, immanent, and conceptual). He probably identifies transcendent universals as divine ideas, and accepts too forms immanent in corporeal particulars, most likely construing these along the Aphrodisian lines that he hints at in a well-known passage from his second commentary on Porphyry's Isagoge. Boethius never states the theory of the three-fold form ou…Read more
  •  71
    Idolatry and Religious Language
    Faith and Philosophy 25 (2): 190-196. 2008.
    Upholding a univocity theory of religious language does not entail idolatry, because nothing about univocity entails misidentifying God altogether—which is what idolatry amounts to. Upholders and opponents of univocity can agree on the object to which they are ascribing various attributes, even if they do not agree on the attributes themselves. Neither does the defender of univocity have to maintain that there is anything real really shared by God and creatures. Furthermore, even if much of lang…Read more