•  10
    Reasons to Dwell on (if Not Necessarily in) the Suburbs
    Environmental Ethics 26 (1): 77-95. 2004.
    Environmental philosophers should look beyond stereotypes to consider American suburbs as an environment worthy of serious philosophical scrutiny for three reasons. First, for better or worse, the suburbs are the environment of primary concern to most Americans, and suburban patterns of development have caught on elsewhere in the industrialized world. Second, the suburbs are much more of a problem than many environmental theorists suppose, in part because suburban patterns of development are ent…Read more
  •  24
    Reasons to dwell on (if not necessarily in) the suburbs
    Environmental Ethics 26 (1): 77-95. 2004.
    Environmental philosophers should look beyond stereotypes to consider American suburbs as an environment worthy of serious philosophical scrutiny for three reasons. First, for better or worse, the suburbs are the environment of primary concern to most Americans, and suburban patterns of development have caught on elsewhere in the industrialized world. Second, the suburbs are much more of a problem than many environmental theorists suppose, in part because suburban patterns of development are ent…Read more
  •  31
    Why Ecology Cannot Be All Things to All People
    Environmental Ethics 19 (4): 375-390. 1997.
    On the basis of a model of the development of scientific concepts as analogous to the “adaptive radiation” of organisms, I raise questions concerning the speculative project of many environmental philosophers, especially insofar as that project reflects on the relationship between ecology (the science) and ecologism (the worldview or ideology). This relationship is often understood in terms of anopposition to the “modern” worldview, which leads to the identification of ecology as an ally or as a…Read more
  •  5
    At Home in the Seamless Web: Agency, Obduracy, and the Ethics of Metropolitan Growth
    Science, Technology, and Human Values 34 (2): 234-258. 2009.
    Political responses to metropolitan growth in the United States and elsewhere should include careful ethical deliberation, but ethical judgment and action are limited by the involvement of individual moral agents in the complex processes that give shape to the built environment. I propose that casting the built environment as a heterogeneous sociotechnical ensemble can provide useful insight into the limits of ethics, particularly through the concept of obduracy. To the extent components of an e…Read more
  •  53
    Did Americans Choose Sprawl?
    Ethics and the Environment 15 (1): 123. 2010.
    In the debate over urban sprawl in the United States, there is serious contention concerning its origins: Does sprawl exist because of or in spite of peoples' values and choices? As the debate plays out, it becomes clear that this question has only partly to do with the historical causes of sprawl and much more to do with questions of political legitimacy in decisions about the built environment. It also becomes clear that the debate as currently framed is not very fruitful. One way of getting a…Read more
  •  39
    The Engineering and Science Issues Test (ESIT): A Discipline-Specific Approach to Assessing Moral Judgment (review)
    with Jason Borenstein, Matthew J. Drake, and Julie L. Swann
    Science and Engineering Ethics 16 (2): 387-407. 2010.
    To assess ethics pedagogy in science and engineering, we developed a new tool called the Engineering and Science Issues Test (ESIT). ESIT measures moral judgment in a manner similar to the Defining Issues Test, second edition, but is built around technical dilemmas in science and engineering. We used a quasi-experimental approach with pre- and post-tests, and we compared the results to those of a control group with no overt ethics instruction. Our findings are that several (but not all) stand-al…Read more
  •  16
    The “tuning-in” relationship in music and in ethics
    Continental Philosophy Review 56 (2): 279-293. 2023.
    In “Making Music Together: A Study in Social Relationship,” Alfred Schutz offers a phenomenological description of a structure he contends is at the root not only of shared musical meaning, but of human communication and social relations as such: the “tuning-in relationship.” The aim of what follows is to establish that this same structure is at the root of ethical relationships, which may shed some light on the conditions under which it is possible to respond appropriately to ethically fraught …Read more
  • Environmentalism Without Illusions: Redefining the Roles of Philosophy and Ecology
    Dissertation, State University of New York at Stony Brook. 1995.
    To express concern for our "relationship" with our environment is immediately to raise the questions of what our environment is and what sort of relationship we do--or ought to--have with it. While environmental thinkers frequently make broad factual and normative claims about our environment, I argue that these claims are usually based on a profound misunderstanding of the scope and limits of human knowledge; specifically, they overlook the ambiguity of our knowledge of our environment in favor…Read more
  •  6
    Getting a Feel for Systems
    Teaching Ethics 20 (1-2): 1-13. 2020.
    In response to the challenges of teaching a course in environmental ethics to engineering majors at a technological university, I have developed an approach that emphasizes the role of moral imagination in conjunction with systems imagination in responding to problems that arise in shared environments. The course is set out on a model of problem-based learning, conceived as a cognitive apprenticeship: by working together to understand and consider responses to problems that are of interest to th…Read more
  •  8
    Getting a Feel for Systems
    Teaching Ethics 20 (1-2): 1-13. 2020.
    In response to the challenges of teaching a course in environmental ethics to engineering majors at a technological university, I have developed an approach that emphasizes the role of moral imagination in conjunction with systems imagination in responding to problems that arise in shared environments. The course is set out on a model of problem-based learning, conceived as a cognitive apprenticeship: by working together to understand and consider responses to problems that are of interest to th…Read more
  •  10
    In Skeptical Environmentalism, Robert Kirkman raises doubts about the speculative tendencies elaborated in environmental ethics, deep ecology, social ecology, postmodern ecology, ecofeminism, and environmental pragmatism. Drawing on skeptical principles introduced by David Hume, Kirkman takes issue with key tenets of speculative environmentalism, namely that the natural world is fundamentally relational, that humans have a moral obligation to protect the order of nature, and that understanding t…Read more
  •  9
    Earth Ways: Framing Geographical Meanings (edited book)
    with Deepanwita Dasgupta, Jason W. Moore, François-Xavier Nzi Iyo Nsenga, Lawrence A. Peskin, Dennis E. Skocz, and Paul Steege
    Lexington Books. 2004.
    How do you connect the discipline of anthropology to both philosophy and geography? What about history, sociology, and other applied and theoretical forms of knowledge? In Earth Ways: Framing Geographical Meanings, Gary Backhaus and John Murungi challenge contributors to find the organizing component, or "framings," that enables them to bridge their own work to philosophy and geography. What emerges are truly creative contributions to interdisciplinary thought
  •  57
    Teaching for Moral Imagination
    Teaching Philosophy 31 (4): 333-350. 2008.
    This paper reports the results of an assessment project conducted in a semester-length course in environmental ethics. The first goal of the project was to measure the degree to which the course succeeded in meeting its overarching goal of enriching students’ moral imagination and its more particular objectives relating to ethics in the built environment. The second goal of the project was to contribute toward a broader effort to develop assessment tools for ethics education. Through qualitative…Read more
  •  21
    The Skeptical Environmentalist (review)
    Environmental Ethics 25 (4): 423-426. 2003.
  •  39
    Democracy’s Dilemma (review)
    Environmental Ethics 26 (3): 331-332. 2004.
  •  32
    Technological momentum and the ethics of metropolitan growth
    Ethics, Place and Environment 7 (3). 2004.
    One goal of environmental ethics is to recommend changes to patterns of human life so as to bring inhabited landscapes into line with a vision of the good. However, the complex intertwining of nature and culture in inhabited landscapes makes this project much more difficult, complicating ethical judgment and limiting the efficacy of ethical action. Technological momentum, a model introduced by historian Thomas P. Hughes to describe the development of complex technological systems, can shed some …Read more
  •  23
    Ethics and Scale in the Built Environment
    Environmental Philosophy 2 (2): 38-52. 2005.
    On the way to a phenomenology of the moral space within which people make decisions about the built environments they inhabit, I take up Bryan Norton’s proposal for a non-linear, multi-scalar approach to environmental ethics. Inspired by a recent development in ecology, hierarchy theory, Norton’s key insight is that ethical concerns play themselves out across distinct spatio-temporal scales. I adapt this insight to the context of the built environment by way of a phenomenology of constraint as a…Read more
  • The Skeptical Environmentalist (review)
    Environmental Ethics 25 (4): 423-426. 2003.
  •  5
    Review of John R. E. Bliese. The Greening of Conservative America (review)
    Environmental Ethics 25 (2): 221-222. 2003.
  •  33
    Ethical choice and action in the built environment are complicated by the fact that moral agents often get stuck as they pursue their goals. A common way of getting stuck has its roots in human cognition: the failure of moral imagination, which shows most clearly when moral agents stand on either side of a sharp cultural divide, like the traditional divide between city and suburb. Being stuck is akin to bad moral luck: it is a situation beyond the control of the moral agent for which that agent …Read more
  •  21
    Navigating Bioethical Waters: Two Pilot Projects in Problem-Based Learning for Future Bioscience and Biotechnology Professionals
    with Roberta M. Berry, Aaron D. Levine, Laura Palucki Blake, and Matthew Drake
    Science and Engineering Ethics 22 (6): 1649-1667. 2016.
    We believe that the professional responsibility of bioscience and biotechnology professionals includes a social responsibility to contribute to the resolution of ethically fraught policy problems generated by their work. It follows that educators have a professional responsibility to prepare future professionals to discharge this responsibility. This essay discusses two pilot projects in ethics pedagogy focused on particularly challenging policy problems, which we call “fractious problems”. The …Read more
  •  18
    The New Ecological Order (review)
    Environmental Ethics 20 (1): 101-104. 1998.
  •  110
  •  46
    Environmental Justice and the New Pluralism (review)
    Environmental Ethics 23 (1): 109-110. 2001.
  •  29
    The Green State (review)
    Environmental Ethics 27 (4): 437-440. 2004.
  •  9
    Darwinian Humanism and the End of Nature
    Environmental Values 18 (2). 2009.
    Darwinian humanism proposes that environmental philosophers pursue their work in full recognition of an irreducible ambiguity at the heart of human experience: we may legitimately regard moral action as fully free and fully natural at the same time, since neither perspective can be taken as the whole truth. A serious objection to this proposal holds that freedom and nature may be unified as an organic whole, and their unity posited as a matter of substantive truth, by appeal to teleology. In par…Read more