•  167
    The Mental Model Theory of Conditionals: A Reply to Guy Politzer (review)
    with Philip N. Johnson-Laird and Vittorio Girotto
    Topoi 28 (1): 75-80. 2009.
    This paper replies to Politzer’s (2007) criticisms of the mental model theory of conditionals. It argues that the theory provides a correct account of negation of conditionals, that it does not provide a truth-functional account of their meaning, though it predicts that certain interpretations of conditionals yield acceptable versions of the ‘paradoxes’ of material implication, and that it postulates three main strategies for estimating the probabilities of conditionals.
  •  15
    “If only” counterfactual thoughts about cooperative and uncooperative decisions in social dilemmas
    with Stefania Pighin and Katya Tentori
    Thinking and Reasoning 28 (2): 193-225. 2022.
    We examined how people think about how things could have turned out differently after they made a decision to cooperate or not in three social interactions: the Prisoner’s dilemma (Experiment 1), the Stag Hunt dilemma (Experiment 2), and the Chicken game (Experiment 3). We found that participants who took part in the game imagined the outcome would have been different if a different decision had been made by the other player, not themselves; they did so whether the outcome was good or bad for th…Read more
  •  22
    The Suppression of Inferences From Counterfactual Conditionals
    with Orlando Espino
    Cognitive Science 44 (4). 2020.
    We examine two competing effects of beliefs on conditional inferences. The suppression effect occurs for conditionals, for example, “if she watered the plants they bloomed,” when beliefs about additional background conditions, for example, “if the sun shone they bloomed” decrease the frequency of inferences such as modus tollens (from “the plants did not bloom” to “therefore she did not water them”). In contrast, the counterfactual elevation effect occurs for counterfactual conditionals, for exa…Read more
  •  33
    When people understand a counterfactual such as “if the flowers had been roses, the trees would have been orange trees,” they think about the conjecture, “there were roses and orange trees,” and they also think about its opposite, the presupposed facts. We test whether people think about the opposite by representing alternates, for example, “poppies and apple trees,” or whether models can contain symbols, for example, “no roses and no orange trees.” We report the discovery of an inference‐to‐alt…Read more
  •  7
    Thoughts about Exceptional Events
    In Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack & Sarah R. Beck (eds.), Understanding Counterfactuals, Understanding Causation, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  53
    Suppressing valid inferences with conditionals
    Cognition 31 (1): 61-83. 1989.
    Three experiments are reported which show that in certain contexts subjects reject instances of the valid modus ponens and modus tollens inference form in conditional arguments. For example, when a conditional premise, such as: If she meets her friend then she will go to a play, is accompanied by a conditional containing an additional requirement: If she has enough money then she will go to a play, subjects reject the inference from the categorical premise: She meets her friend, to the conclusio…Read more
  •  16
    The mental representation of what might have been
    with Clare R. Walsh
    In David R. Mandel, Denis J. Hilton & Patrizia Catellani (eds.), The Psychology of Counterfactual Thinking, Routledge. 2005.
  •  45
    Facts and Possibilities: A Model‐Based Theory of Sentential Reasoning
    with Sangeet S. Khemlani and Philip N. Johnson-Laird
    Cognitive Science 42 (6): 1887-1924. 2018.
    This article presents a fundamental advance in the theory of mental models as an explanation of reasoning about facts, possibilities, and probabilities. It postulates that the meanings of compound assertions, such as conditionals (if) and disjunctions (or), unlike those in logic, refer to conjunctions of epistemic possibilities that hold in default of information to the contrary. Various factors such as general knowledge can modulate these interpretations. New information can always override sen…Read more
  •  32
    Moral hindsight for good actions and the effects of imagined alternatives to reality
    with Shane Timmons
    Cognition 178 (C): 82-91. 2018.
  •  14
    Inferences from disclosures about the truth and falsity of expert testimony
    with Sergio Moreno-Ríos
    Thinking and Reasoning 24 (1): 41-78. 2018.
    Participants acting as mock jurors made inferences about whether a person was a suspect in a murder based on an expert's testimony about the presence of objects at the crime scene and the disclosure that the testimony was true or false. Experiment 1 showed that participants made more correct inferences, and made inferences more quickly, when the truth or falsity of the expert's testimony was disclosed immediately after the testimony rather than when the disclosure was delayed. Experiment 2 showe…Read more
  •  45
    Counterfactual and semi-factual thoughts in moral judgements about failed attempts to harm
    with Mary Parkinson
    Thinking and Reasoning 23 (4): 409-448. 2017.
    People judge that an individual who attempts to harm someone but fails should be blamed and punished more when they imagine how things could have turned out worse, compared to when they imagine how things could have turned out the same, or when they think only about what happened. This moral counterfactual amplification effect occurs when people believe the protagonist had no reason for the attempt to harm, and not when the protagonist had a reason, as Experiment 1 shows. It occurs for intention…Read more
  • Priming Causal Conditionals
    with Caren A. Frosch
  •  20
    Reasoning from Suppositions
    with Simon J. Handley and Philip N. Johnson-Laird
    Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology Section A 48 (4): 915-944. 1995.
    Two experiments investigated inferences based on suppositions. In Experiment 1, the subjects decided whether suppositions about individuals' veracity were consistent with their assertions—for example, whether the supposition “Ann is telling the truth and Beth is telling a lie”, is consistent with the premises: “Ann asserts: I am telling the truth and Beth is telling the truth. Beth asserts: Ann is telling the truth”. It showed that these inferences are more difficult than ones based on factual p…Read more
  •  56
    Conditionals: A theory of meaning, pragmatics, and inference
    with Philip Johnson-Laird
    Psychological Review 109 (4): 646-678. 2002.
    The authors outline a theory of conditionals of the form If A then C and If A then possibly C. The 2 sorts of conditional have separate core meanings that refer to sets of possibilities. Knowledge, pragmatics, and semantics can modulate these meanings. Modulation can add information about temporal and other relations between antecedent and consequent. It can also prevent the construction of possibilities to yield 10 distinct sets of possibilities to which conditionals can refer. The mental repre…Read more
  •  33
    Deduction
    with Philip Nicholas Johnson-Laird
    Psychology Press. 1991.
    In this study on deduction, the authors argue that people reason by imagining the relevant state of affairs, ie building an internal model of it, formulating a tentative conclusion based on this model and then searching for alternative models.
  •  46
    Dual processes of emotion and reason in judgments about moral dilemmas
    with Eoin Gubbins
    Thinking and Reasoning 20 (2): 245-268. 2014.
    We report the results of two experiments that show that participants rely on both emotion and reason in moral judgments. Experiment 1 showed that when participants were primed to communicate feelings, they provided emotive justifications not only for personal dilemmas, e.g., pushing a man from a bridge that will result in his death but save the lives of five others, but also for impersonal dilemmas, e.g., hitting a switch on a runaway train that will result in the death of one man but save the l…Read more
  •  21
  •  70
    Précis of Deduction
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2): 323-333. 1993.
    How do people make deductions? The orthodox view in psychology is that they use formal rules of inference like those of a “natural deduction” system.Deductionargues that their logical competence depends, not on formal rules, but on mental models. They construct models of the situation described by the premises, using their linguistic knowledge and their general knowledge. They try to formulate a conclusion based on these models that maintains semantic information, that expresses it parsimoniousl…Read more
  •  32
    Mental models and syllogisms
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (3): 543-546. 1996.
    We resolve the two problems that Hardman raises. The first problem arises from a misunderstanding: the crucial distinction is between one-model and multiple-model problems. The second problem illuminates a deeper principle: conclusions depend on the procedures for interpreting models. We describe an algorithm that obviates the problem and empirical work that reveals a new view of syllogistic reasoning
  •  72
    Counterfactual thoughts about experienced, observed, and narrated events
    with Stefania Pighin, Donatella Ferrante, Michel Gonzalez, and Vittorio Girotto
    Thinking and Reasoning 17 (2). 2011.
    Four studies show that observers and readers imagine different alternatives to reality. When participants read a story about a protagonist who chose the more difficult of two tasks and failed, their counterfactual thoughts focused on the easier, unchosen task. But when they observed the performance of an individual who chose and failed the more difficult task, participants' counterfactual thoughts focused on alternative ways to solve the chosen task, as did the thoughts of individuals who acted …Read more
  •  146
    A leading scholar in the psychology of thinking and reasoning argues that the counterfactual imagination—the creation of "if only" alternatives to ...