Serena Olsaretti

ICREA & Universitat Pompeu Fabra
  • Justice, Luck, and Desert
    In John S. Dryzek, Bonnie Honig & Anne Phillips (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Theory, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This article examines the relation among luck, justice, and desert in the context of contemporary political theory. The distinctive feature of the conventional view of desert-based justice consists in its claim that we deserve on the basis of our achievements, the outcome of our actions, or the quality of our performances. One challenge to the conventional view's treatment of the relation between justice, luck, and desert comes from those who hold that desert-based justice is compatible with mor…Read more
  •  8
    Preferences are often thought to be relevant for well-being: respecting preferences, or satisfying them, contributes in some way to making people's lives go well for them. A crucial assumption that accompanies this conviction is that there is a normative standard that allows us to discriminate between preferences that do, and those that do not, contribute to well-being. The papers collected in this volume, written by moral philosophers and philosophers of economics, explore a number of central i…Read more
  •  33
  •  8
    A Non-Remedial Case for a Temporary Migration Package?
    Law, Ethics and Philosophy 9 114-128. 2023.
  •  50
    Why Socializing the Costs of Children Is Fair to Parents: A Rejoinder to Hohl
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 50 (4): 413-429. 2022.
    Philosophy &Public Affairs, Volume 50, Issue 4, Page 413-429, Fall 2022.
  •  26
    Justice, markets, and the family: an interview with Serena Olsaretti
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 9 (2): 181. 2016.
  •  45
    Children as negative externalities?
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 16 (2): 152-173. 2017.
    Egalitarian theories assume, without defending it, the view that the costs of children should be shared between non-parents and parents. This standard position is called into question by the Parental Provision view. Drawing on the familiar idea that people should be held responsible for the consequences of their choices, the Parental Provision view holds that under certain conditions egalitarian justice requires parents to pay for the full costs of their children, as it would be unfair for non-p…Read more
  •  232
    Responsibility and the consequences of choice
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1pt2): 165-188. 2009.
    Contemporary egalitarian theories of justice constrain the demands of equality by responsibility, and do not view as unjust inequalities that are traceable to individuals' choices. This paper argues that, in order to make non-arbitrary determinate judgements of responsibility, any theory of justice needs a principle of stakes , that is, an account of what consequences choices should have. The paper also argues that the principles of stakes seemingly presupposed by egalitarians are implausible, a…Read more
  •  54
    Liberty, Desert and the Market: A Philosophical Study
    Cambridge University Press. 2004.
    Are inequalities of income created by the free market just? In this book Serena Olsaretti examines two main arguments that justify those inequalities: the first claims that they are just because they are deserved, and the second claims that they are just because they are what free individuals are entitled to. Both these arguments purport to show, in different ways, that giving responsible individuals their due requires that free market inequalities in incomes be allowed. Olsaretti argues, howeve…Read more
  •  2
    The compensatory desert argument is an argument that purports to justify inequalities in (some) incomes generated by a free labour market. It holds, first, that the principle of compensation is a principle of desert; second, that a distribution justified by a principle of desert is just; and third, that (some) rewards people reap on a free labour market are compensation for costs they incur. It concludes that therefore, a distribution of (some) rewards generated by a free labour market is just. …Read more
  •  88
    Equality of resources and the demands of authenticity
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (4): 434-455. 2016.
    One of the most distinctive features of Ronald Dworkin’s egalitarian theory is its commitment to holding individuals responsible for the costs to others of their ambitions. This commitment has received much criticism. Drawing on Dworkin’s latest statement of his position in Justice for Hedgehogs (2011), we suggest that it seems to be in tension with another crucial element of Dworkin’s own theory, namely, its endorsement of the importance of people leading authentic lives – lives that reflect th…Read more
  •  137
    The Limits of Hedonism: Feldman on the Value of Attitudinal Pleasure
    Philosophical Studies 136 (3): 409-415. 2007.
    This paper is part of a book symposium on Fred Feldman's, *Pleasure and the Good Life*. I argue that Feldman’s defence of hedonism, although successful on its own terms, is of less significance than it may seem at first, for two main reasons. First, Feldman’s defence of the claim that attitudinal pleasures are the chief good is either implausible or crucially incomplete. Second, Feldman’s claim that hedonists can overcome the objections levelled against them while remaining pure hedonists is on…Read more
  •  30
    : Bottlenecks: A New Theory of Equal Opportunity (review)
    Ethics 126 (3): 821-825. 2016.
  •  187
    Coercion and libertarianism: a reply to Gordon Barnes
    Analysis 73 (2): 295-299. 2013.
    Libertarians oppose coercion and champion a free-market society. Are these two commitments, as libertarians claim, wholly consistent with one another, or is there, by contrast, a tension between them? This paper defends the latter view. Replying to an article by Gordon Barnes, the paper casts doubts on the success of an argument aimed at establishing that, while coercion is justice-disrupting, all non-coercive but forced transactions that occur in a free market are justice-preserving
  •  78
    Rescuing justice and equality from libertarianism
    Economics and Philosophy 29 (1): 43-63. 2013.
    One of the central motifs of G. A. Cohen's work was his opposition to capitalism in the name of justice. This motif was fully in view in Cohen's work on Robert Nozick's libertarianism: Cohen carefully reconstructed and relentlessly criticized Nozick's apologetics of the free market, which, he thought, was internally coherent but unconvincing. This article suggests that Cohen's opposition to libertarianism did not, however, go far enough, and identifies two respects in which Cohen's position coul…Read more
  •  121
    Endorsement and freedom in Amartya Sen's capability approach
    Economics and Philosophy 21 (1): 89-108. 2005.
    A central question for assessing the merits of Amartya Sen's capability approach as a potential answer to the “distribution of what”? question concerns the exact role and nature of freedom in that approach. Sen holds that a person's capability identifies that person's effective freedom to achieve valuable states of beings and doings, or functionings, and that freedom so understood, rather than achieved functionings themselves, is the primary evaluative space. Sen's emphasis on freedom has been c…Read more
  •  77
    The Oxford Handbook of Distributive Justice (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
    Distributive justice has come to the fore in political philosophy: how should we arrange our social and economic institutions so as to distribute benefits and burdens fairly? Thirty-two leading figures from philosophy and political theory present specially written critical assessments of the key issues in this flourishing area of research.
  •  325
    Children as Public Goods?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 41 (3): 226-258. 2013.
  •  100
  •  102
    Scanlon on Responsibility and the Value of Choice
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (4): 465-483. 2013.
    This paper examines Thomas Scanlon’s Value of Choice account of substantive responsibility, on which the fact that choice has value accounts both for why people should be provided with certain opportunities and for why it may be permissible, in those cases, to let people bear certain opportunity-accompanying burdens. Scanlon contrasts his view with the familiar one according to which it is permissible to require people to bear certain burdens if and only if they have actively chosen those burden…Read more