Serena Olsaretti

ICREA & Universitat Pompeu Fabra
  • Justice, Luck, and Desert
    In John S. Dryzek, Bonnie Honig & Anne Phillips (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Theory, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    This article examines the relation among luck, justice, and desert in the context of contemporary political theory. The distinctive feature of the conventional view of desert-based justice consists in its claim that we deserve on the basis of our achievements, the outcome of our actions, or the quality of our performances. One challenge to the conventional view's treatment of the relation between justice, luck, and desert comes from those who hold that desert-based justice is compatible with mor…Read more
  •  8
    Preferences are often thought to be relevant for well-being: respecting preferences, or satisfying them, contributes in some way to making people's lives go well for them. A crucial assumption that accompanies this conviction is that there is a normative standard that allows us to discriminate between preferences that do, and those that do not, contribute to well-being. The papers collected in this volume, written by moral philosophers and philosophers of economics, explore a number of central i…Read more
  •  33
  •  8
    A Non-Remedial Case for a Temporary Migration Package?
    Law, Ethics and Philosophy 9 114-128. 2023.
  •  50
    Why Socializing the Costs of Children Is Fair to Parents: A Rejoinder to Hohl
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 50 (4): 413-429. 2022.
    Philosophy &Public Affairs, Volume 50, Issue 4, Page 413-429, Fall 2022.
  •  26
    Justice, markets, and the family: an interview with Serena Olsaretti
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 9 (2): 181. 2016.
  •  45
    Children as negative externalities?
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 16 (2): 152-173. 2017.
    Egalitarian theories assume, without defending it, the view that the costs of children should be shared between non-parents and parents. This standard position is called into question by the Parental Provision view. Drawing on the familiar idea that people should be held responsible for the consequences of their choices, the Parental Provision view holds that under certain conditions egalitarian justice requires parents to pay for the full costs of their children, as it would be unfair for non-p…Read more
  •  187
    Coercion and libertarianism: a reply to Gordon Barnes
    Analysis 73 (2): 295-299. 2013.
    Libertarians oppose coercion and champion a free-market society. Are these two commitments, as libertarians claim, wholly consistent with one another, or is there, by contrast, a tension between them? This paper defends the latter view. Replying to an article by Gordon Barnes, the paper casts doubts on the success of an argument aimed at establishing that, while coercion is justice-disrupting, all non-coercive but forced transactions that occur in a free market are justice-preserving
  •  78
    Rescuing justice and equality from libertarianism
    Economics and Philosophy 29 (1): 43-63. 2013.
    One of the central motifs of G. A. Cohen's work was his opposition to capitalism in the name of justice. This motif was fully in view in Cohen's work on Robert Nozick's libertarianism: Cohen carefully reconstructed and relentlessly criticized Nozick's apologetics of the free market, which, he thought, was internally coherent but unconvincing. This article suggests that Cohen's opposition to libertarianism did not, however, go far enough, and identifies two respects in which Cohen's position coul…Read more
  •  121
    Endorsement and freedom in Amartya Sen's capability approach
    Economics and Philosophy 21 (1): 89-108. 2005.
    A central question for assessing the merits of Amartya Sen's capability approach as a potential answer to the “distribution of what”? question concerns the exact role and nature of freedom in that approach. Sen holds that a person's capability identifies that person's effective freedom to achieve valuable states of beings and doings, or functionings, and that freedom so understood, rather than achieved functionings themselves, is the primary evaluative space. Sen's emphasis on freedom has been c…Read more
  •  77
    The Oxford Handbook of Distributive Justice (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
    Distributive justice has come to the fore in political philosophy: how should we arrange our social and economic institutions so as to distribute benefits and burdens fairly? Thirty-two leading figures from philosophy and political theory present specially written critical assessments of the key issues in this flourishing area of research.
  •  325
    Children as Public Goods?
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 41 (3): 226-258. 2013.
  •  100
  •  102
    Scanlon on Responsibility and the Value of Choice
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (4): 465-483. 2013.
    This paper examines Thomas Scanlon’s Value of Choice account of substantive responsibility, on which the fact that choice has value accounts both for why people should be provided with certain opportunities and for why it may be permissible, in those cases, to let people bear certain opportunity-accompanying burdens. Scanlon contrasts his view with the familiar one according to which it is permissible to require people to bear certain burdens if and only if they have actively chosen those burden…Read more
  •  17
    Measuring Justice (review)
    Social Theory and Practice 38 (1): 180-186. 2012.
  •  102
    Liberal Egalitarianism and Workfare
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (3): 257-270. 2004.
    In this paper we ask whether liberal egalitarians can endorse workfare policies that require that welfare recipients should work in return for their welfare benefits. In particular, we focus on the fairness-based case for workfare, which holds that people should be responsible for their own welfare since they would otherwise impose unfair costs on others. Two versions of the fairness-based case are considered: The first defends workfare on the grounds that it would form part of an unemployment i…Read more
  •  11
    Preferences and Well-Being (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    Preferences are often thought to be relevant for well-being: respecting preferences, or satisfying them, contributes in some way to making people's lives go well for them. A crucial assumption that accompanies this conviction is that there is a normative standard that allows us to discriminate between preferences that do, and those that do not, contribute to well-being. The papers collected in this volume, written by moral philosophers and philosophers of economics, explore a number of central i…Read more
  •  17
    Introduction
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 1-8. 2006.
    In a number of debates in contemporary moral and political philosophy and philosophy of economics, philosophers hold the conviction that preferences have normative significance. A central assumption that underlies this conviction is that a cogent account of preference-formation can be developed. This is particularly evident in debates about well-being. Those who defend subjective accounts of well-being, on which a person’s life goes better for her to the extent that her preferences are satisfied…Read more
  •  176
    Desert and justice (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2003.
    Does justice require that individuals get what they deserve? Serena Olsaretti brings together new essays by leading moral and political philosophers examining the relation between desert and justice; they also illuminate the nature of distributive justice, and the relationship between desert and other values, such as equality and responsibility.