•  207
    The determinists have run out of luck—for a good reason
    with E. J. Lowe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 745-748. 2008.
    In his paper ‘‘Bad luck once again’’ Neil Levy attacks our proof of the consistency of libertarianism by reiterating a time-worn compatibilist complaint.1 This is, that what is not determined must be due to chance. If A has a choice of X or Y, neither X nor Y being causally determined, then if A chooses X it can only be by chance, never for a reason. The only ‘‘reason’’ that could explain the choice of X over Y would have to be a causally sufficient reason, which would rule out A’s having a genuin…Read more
  •  99
    Connexive implication
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3): 415-433. 1966.
  •  16
    La Logique du Temps
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (3): 430-432. 1977.
  •  131
    Indeterminist free will
    with E. J. Lowe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3). 2005.
    The aim of the paper is to prove the consistency of libertarianism. We examine the example of Jane, who deliberates at length over whether to vacation in Colorado (C) or Hawaii (H), weighing the costs and benefits, consulting travel brochures, etc. Underlying phenomenological deliberation is an indeterministic neural process in which nonactual motor neural states n(C) and n(H) corresponding to alternatives C and H remain physically possible up until the moment of decision. The neurophysiological…Read more
  •  30
    Indeterminist Free Will
    with E. J. Lowe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3): 681-690. 2007.
    The aim of the paper is to prove the consistency of libertarianism. We examine the example of Jane, who deliberates at length over whether to vacation in Colorado (C) or Hawaii (H), weighing the costs and benefits, consulting travel brochures, etc. Underlying phenomenological deliberation is an indeterministic neural process in which nonactual motor neural states n(C) and n(H) corresponding to alternatives C and H remain physically possible up until the moment of decision. The neurophysiological…Read more
  •  15
    The Ontology of Time (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1): 225-228. 2008.
  •  8
    Logical Works
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3): 873-874. 1983.
  •  3
    Fate, Logic and Time (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 65 (22): 742-746. 1968.
  •  116
    Model of the Universe
    Oxford University Press UK. 1996.
    Storrs McCall presents an original philosophical theory of the nature of the universe based on a striking new model of its space- time structure. He shows how his model illuminates a broad range of subjects, including causation, probability, quantum mechanics, identity, and free will, and argues that the fact that the model throws light on such a large number of problems constitutes strong evidence that the universe is as the model portrays it.
  •  19
    ABSTRACT In their contribution to the first part of this special issue Craig Bourn and Emily Caddick Bourne claim to have solved a puzzle I put forward in my ‘An Insoluble Problem’. Here I argue that their attempt fails.
  • Polish Logic 1920-1939
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 160 495-495. 1970.
  •  13
    Pure Three-Valued Łukasiewiczian Implication
    with R. K. Meyer
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1): 133-134. 1968.
  •  18
    God's lottery
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 49 (4): 223. 1989.
  •  6
    The Determinists Have Run Out of Luck---For a Good Reason
    with E. Lowe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 745-748. 2008.
  •  90
    The ontology of time
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (1). 2008.
  •  7
    Critical notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (4): 663-680. 1985.
  •  37
    Starting and Stopping.Instants and Intervals
    with C. L. Hamblin, J. T. Fraser, F. C. Haber, and G. H. Muller
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (1): 99. 1975.
  •  122
    A dynamic model of temporal becoming
    Analysis 44 (4): 172-176. 1984.
  •  31
    Pure three-valued łukasiewiczian implication
    with R. K. Meyer
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3): 399-405. 1966.
  •  30
    Incline Without Necessitating
    Dialogue 24 (4): 589-. 1985.
    A stranger runs out of a bank while I am sitting at the wheel of my car waiting for the lights to change; he jumps in beside me, points a gun at me, and says, “Drive me to St. Bruno.” This is Andre Gombay's example, from his excellent paper on duress. The question that interests Gombay and me is: Could I refrain from doing what the gunman asks?
  •  228
    Does the Brain Lead the Mind?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (2): 262-265. 2013.
    Over the last 25 years, experimental findings published by Benjamin Libet have indicated that conscious acts of will are preceded by a characteristic kind of brain event of which the agent is not conscious. It, Libet says, rather than the will, is what causes actions. His discoveries, if correct, would seem to imply that the notion of a free, conscious will is an illusion, and that actions are initiated by neural processes not under conscious control. In what follows it is argued that Libet’s co…Read more
  •  289
    The definition of endurance
    with E. J. Lowe
    Analysis 69 (2): 277-280. 2009.
    David Lewis, following in the tradition of Broad, Quine and Goodman, says that change in an object X consists in X's being temporally extended and having qualitatively different temporal parts. Analogously, change in a spatially extended object such as a road consists in its having different spatial parts . The alternative to this view is that ordinary objects undergo temporal change in virtue of having different intrinsic non-relational properties at different times. They endure, remaining the …Read more