•  1
    Having watched totalitarianism emerge in its left-wing (Russian Soviet) and right-wing (Nazi) forms, Michael Polanyi devoted considerable attention to analysing totalitarianism in its development, makeup and mode of operation. At the same time as he developed his account of totalitarianism incrementally he pieced together his picture of liberalism. His fundamental insight is that while liberal civilization is dedicated to protecting, and is animated by, a set of ideals that includes freedom, tru…Read more
  •  603
    Michael Polanyi and Karl Mannheim
    Tradition and Discovery 32 (1): 20-43. 2005.
    This essay reviews historical records that set forth the discussions and interaction of Michael Polanyi and Karl Mannheim/rom 1944 until Mannheim’s death early in 1947. The letters describe Polanyi’s effort to assemble a book to be published in a series edited by Manneheim. Theyalso reveal the different perspectives these thinkers took about freedom and the historical context of ideas. Records of J.H. Oldham’s discussion group “the Moot” suggest that these and other differences in philosophy wer…Read more
  •  25
    In his writings between 1941 and 1951, Michael Polanyi developed a distinctive view of liberal social and political life. Planned organizations are a part of all modern societies, according to Polanyi, but in liberal modernity he highlighted dynamic social orders whose agents freely adjust their efforts in light of the initiatives and accomplishments of their peers. Liberal society itself is the most extensive of dynamic orders, with the market economy, and cultural orders of scientific research…Read more
  •  56
    Relations between Karl Popper and Michael Polanyi
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (3): 426-435. 2011.
  •  32
    Friedrich Hayek and Michael Polanyi in Correspondence
    History of European Ideas 42 (1): 107-130. 2016.
    SummaryFriedrich Hayek and Michael Polanyi corresponded with each other for the best part of thirty years. They had shared interests that included science, social science, economics, epistemology, history of ideas and political philosophy. Studying their correspondence and related writings, this article shows that Hayek and Polanyi were committed Liberals but with different understandings of liberty, the forces that endanger liberty, and the policies required to rescue it.
  •  20
    Anthropological Materials in the Making of Michael Polanyi’s Metascience
    Perspectives on Science 25 (2): 261-285. 2017.
    Anthropological discussions were important for Michael Polanyi in the middle phase of his intellectual career, in which he articulated in some detail his understanding of science, culture and society. This middle period commenced with his 1946 Riddell Memorial Lectures at Durham University in early 1946, published as Science, Faith and Society later that year, and extended through the publication of Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy in 1958, based on Polanyi’s 1951 and 1952 …Read more
  •  12
    Book reviews (review)
    with Lorraine Code, Deepanwita Dasgupta, Charles R. Twardy, and Rafaela Hillerbrand
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (1). 2008.
  •  32
    Book reviews (review)
    with Susan Tridgell, Reg Naulty, Robert Larmer, Jennifer Welchman, Christopher Lundgren, Adrian Walsh, John Makeham, and Muhammad Kamal
    Sophia 43 (2): 129-147. 2004.
  •  7
    Recovering the Thought of Edward Shils
    Tradition and Discovery 47 (3): 4-13. 2021.
    This article provides an extended review of The Calling of Social Thought, a collection of essays about the thought of social theorist Edward Shils. The article includes preliminary observations about Shils’ life and work, brief summaries of the essays included in the collection, and several suggestions aimed at encouraging additional study of Shils’ writings.
  •  87
    Rationalism and tradition: The Popper–Oakeshott conversation
    with Ian Tregenza
    European Journal of Political Theory 13 (1): 3-24. 2014.
    In 1948 Karl Popper sent a copy of his paper, ‘Utopia and Violence’, to Michael Oakeshott. Popper had recently read Oakeshott’s essay ‘Rationalism in Politics’, appreciating its relevance to views he had expressed in The Open Society. Oakeshott wrote to Popper at some length, explaining his thoughts about reason, tradition and kindred matters, to which Popper responded. This paper reproduces these letters and discusses them with reference to pertinent writings of Popper and Oakeshott. While show…Read more
  •  6
    C. P. Snow’s The Two Cultures: Michael Polanyi’s Response and Context
    Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 31 (3): 172-178. 2011.
    C. P. Snow’s “The Two Cultures” controversially contrasted science and literature, suggesting that neither scientists nor literary intellectuals have much in common with, and seldom bother speaking to, the other. Responding to Snow, Michael Polanyi argued that specialization has made modern culture, not twofold but manifold. In his major work, Personal Knowledge, Polanyi explained that branches of modern culture have personal knowing and knowledge in common, and there is extensive cross-pollinat…Read more
  •  55
    Vindicating Universalism
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19 (1): 75-80. 1989.
  •  9
    Book Review: Conquest of Abundance: A Tale of Abstraction Versus the Richness of Being (review)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (3): 386-389. 2006.
  •  18
    The genesis of 'scientific community'
    Social Epistemology 16 (2): 157-168. 2002.
  •  3
    Michael Polanyi, Tacit Cognitive Relativist
    Heythrop Journal 42 (4): 463-479. 2001.
    Celebrated as a theorist of science, and a source of stimulating ideas for theologians and philosophers of religion, Michael Polanyi explicitly denied cognitive relativism. Yet cognitive relativism, this paper suggests, is implied by Polanyi's account of conceptual frameworks and intellectual controversies.In ‘The Stability of Beliefs’ (1952) Polanyi understands conceptual frameworks (science, psychoanalysis, Azande witchcraft, Marxism) as embedded in, and as expressed in the use of, their own l…Read more
  •  75
    Classical and Conservative Liberalism: Burke, Hayek, Polanyi and Others (review)
    Tradition and Discovery 26 (1): 5-15. 1999.
    An extended discussion of Richard Allen’s Beyond Liberalism: The Political Thought of F. A. Hayek & Michael Polanyi in which the book’s prominent themes and arguments are described, and certain inaccuracies and shortcomings noted.
  •  23
    Edward Shils' Theory of Tradition
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 37 (2): 139-162. 2007.
    Edward Shils presented his book Tradition (1981) as the first extensive study of the subject. This article casts light on Shils' multifaceted understanding of tradition, comprising pragmatic, Burkean, veridical, and evolutionist perspectives. His typology of traditions is noted, and his view of institutional bearers of tradition described. In assessing Shils' theory, however, we find that it overreaches, collapsing differences that exist between traditions, transmissions, and the traditional.
  •  40
    Post‐liberalism vs. temperate liberalism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 4 (3): 365-375. 1990.
    John Gray's recent critique of liberalism, and his case for an apparently relativistic ?post?Pyrrhonian?; political philosophy, are shown to be wanting. Weaknesses in Gray's critique are identified and discussed: the characterization of liberalism as universally prescriptive, confusion about whether liberalism is a genuine tradition, and misunderstanding of the relation between conduct and the value of freedom. A formulation of liberalism that is not universalist ("temperate?; liberalism) is off…Read more
  •  48
    Limits to problem solving in science
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3). 2001.
    Popper, Polanyi and Duncker represent the widely held position that theoretical and experimental scientific research are motivated by problems to which discoveries are solutions. According to the argument here, their views are unsupported and - in light of counter-instances, anomalous chance discoveries, and the force of curiosity - over-generalized.
  •  61
    Born in 1918 in New York, awarded a doctorate in analytical chemistry (1944), Leonard K. Nash enjoyed a distinguished career at Harvard, holding a chair of chemistry from 1959 to 1986. Conducting research in thermodynamics and statistical mechanics, Nash authored successful textbooks, some of which remain in print (e.g. Elements of Chemical Thermodynamics, and Elements of Statistical Thermodynamics).This essay describes the theory of science that Nash developed in a book he published in 1963, Th…Read more
  •  19
    Thomas Kuhn’s Memory
    Intellectual History Review 19 (1): 83-101. 2009.
    No abstract
  •  54
    Spontaneous order: Michael Polanyi and Friedrich Hayek
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 3 (4): 49-67. 2000.
    This paper compares Hayek and Polanyi on spontaneous social order. Although Hayek is widely believed to have first both coined the name and explicated the idea of ?spontaneous order?, it is in fact Michael Polanyi who did so. Numerous differences emerge between the two thinkers. The characterisation of spontaneous order in Hayek, for example, involves different types of freedom to those advanced by Polanyi. Whereas Hayek (usually) portrays spontaneous order as a single entity, which is equivalen…Read more
  •  19
    Michael Polanyi, tacit cognitive relativist
    Heythrop Journal 42 (4). 2001.
    Celebrated as a theorist of science, and a source of stimulating ideas for theologians and philosophers of religion, Michael Polanyi explicitly denied cognitive relativism. Yet cognitive relativism, this paper suggests, is implied by Polanyi's account of conceptual frameworks and intellectual controversies.In ‘The Stability of Beliefs’ Polanyi understands conceptual frameworks as embedded in, and as expressed in the use of, their own languages. The language‐with‐theory limits the range of discus…Read more
  •  50
    Locke, McCann, and voluntarism
    with Allan McNeish
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (4). 1997.
    Locke scholars continue to disagree over how he analyzed natural laws, real essence-power relations in physical substances. Some say he regarded them as emanations, necessitated by the corpuscular structure of real essences; for others his laws are adventitious, imposed on substances by God and contingent on divine alterable will. The second view has been increasingly favored in recent years, assisted no doubt by Edwin McCann's potent case for it in "Lockean Mechanism" (1985). The present articl…Read more
  •  97
    Michael Polanyi argues in Personal Knowledge (1958) that conceptual frameworks involved in major scientific controversies are separated by a `logical gap'. Such frameworks, according to Polanyi (1958: 151), are logically disconnected: their protagonists think differently, use different languages and occupy different worlds. Relinquishing one framework and adopting another, Polanyi's scientist undergoes a `conversion' to a new `faith'. Polanyi, in other words, presaged Kuhn and Feyerabend's conce…Read more
  •  28
  •  125
    Sociology as a source of anomaly in Thomas Kuhn's system of science
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 27 (4): 466-485. 1997.
    It is a testimony to the enduring importance of Thomas Kuhn's The Structure of Scientific Revolutions that, 30 years on, its doctrines of normal science and paradigm, incommensurability and revolution continue to challenge metascien tists and stimulate vigorous debate. Critique has mainly come from philosophers and historians; by and large, interested sociologists have embraced Kuhn. Un justifiably so, this article argues, bringing to light a serious difficulty or "anom aly" in his account of th…Read more