•  2
    Response to Critics
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 59 (4): 432-455. 2024.
    Abstract:This response to a variety of criticisms of Charles Peirce and Modern Science restates and attempts to clarify and explain major themes of the book.
  •  85
    Peirce's Theory of Signs
    Cambridge University Press. 2007.
    In this book, T. L. Short corrects widespread misconceptions of Peirce's theory of signs and demonstrates its relevance to contemporary analytic philosophy of language, mind and science. Peirce's theory of mind, naturalistic but nonreductive, bears on debates of Fodor and Millikan, among others. His theory of inquiry avoids foundationalism and subjectivism, while his account of reference anticipated views of Kripke and Putnam. Peirce's realism falls between 'internal' and 'metaphysical' realism …Read more
  •  7
    Charles Peirce and Modern Science
    Cambridge University Press. 2022.
    In this book, T. L. Short places the notorious difficulties of Peirce's important writings in a more productive light, arguing that he wrote philosophy as a scientist, by framing conjectures intended to be refined or superseded in the inquiries they initiate. He argues also that Peirce held that the methods and metaphysics of modern science are amended as inquiry progresses, making metaphysics a branch of empirical knowledge. Additionally, Short shows that Peirce's scientific work expanded empir…Read more
  •  117
    The Pragmatic Turn by Richard J. Bernstein
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (4): 563-566. 2012.
    Over many decades, Richard Bernstein has interpreted contemporary philosophy’s three traditions, roughly distinguished as analytic, pragmatic, and Continental, emphasizing their mutual affinities. Despite this reference to the continent of Europe, it would be wrong to identify any of these traditions geographically or linguistically; even to call them ‘traditions’ is stretching a point. Pragmatism originated in Cambridge, Massachusetts, but it has spread from there, transmogrifying in the proces…Read more
  •  30
    The 1903 Maxim
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 53 (3): 345. 2017.
    Much has been written on the pragmatic maxim introduced in the 1878 essay 'How to Make Our Ideas Clear'. It was not there so named, but a quarter century later, at the outset of his Lectures on Pragmatism delivered at Harvard in 1903, Peirce quoted it and named it.1 At the conclusion of those lectures occurs another statement named a 'maxim' and implied to be pragmatism's. This 1903 maxim is almost as well-known as the 1878 maxim but has received little comment.2 Was it only a figurative express…Read more
  •  44
    Response
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (4): 663-693. 2007.
    : This response to my seven critics is organized under five topics: 1. The book's scope and approach; 2. Physicalism, idealism, anthropomorphism; 3. Final causation; 4. Peirce's development; 5. Signs, objects, interpretants. No ground is ceded, but I have found the interchange clarifying and hope that the reader will find it so, too
  •  71
    Questions Concerning Certain Claims Made for the ‘New List’
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 49 (3): 267. 2013.
    In May 1867, when he was twenty-seven years of age, Charles Peirce read a paper to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences that was published in the next year under the title ‘On a New List of Categories’ (EP 1:1–10).1 It is remarkable for anticipating major features of his later thought: three categories relationally defined (bracketed, however, by two additional categories); a theory of signs, triadically conceived and triadically sub-divided, applied to thinking; the idea that every predica…Read more
  •  30
    Peirce on Science and Philosophy
    Philosophical Topics 36 (1): 259-277. 2008.
  •  16
    Peirce's Irony
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 54 (1): 9. 2018.
    But as you know... my style of ‘brilliancy’ consists in a mixture of irony and seriousness,—the same things said ironically and also seriously.Peirce’s philosophical writings are notoriously difficult. The reasons most often cited are the apparent contradictions, the long, inconclusive technical digressions, and the unfinished character of his thought. His champions instead emphasize his originality, arguing that his apparent contradictions often mark traditional dualisms subtly transcended; som…Read more
  •  25
    Peirce's Idea of Science
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 56 (2): 212-221. 2020.
    The following paragraphs were written not for print publication but for oral delivery on a celebratory occasion; their many unsupported assertions, some commonplace and some controversial, were made not to prove a thesis but to suggest a point of view—a perspective on Peirce's thought that might be taken, or not, as one wishes. The suggestion is that some difficulties are resolved and some things fall into place if we view his philosophy in its several relations to modern science. For that purpo…Read more
  •  89
    Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism by Paul Forster
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (3): 385-387. 2012.
    This book is remarkable for what it does not do. It purports to be about Peirce's opposition to nominalism, but it never states clearly what nominalism is and says little about Peirce's realist alternative. It contains no historical discussion of nominalism and thus does not explain the relation of Peirce's idiosyncratic use of that term to its original meaning. It ignores the secondary literature on that topic and does not even list Rosa Mayorga's highly relevant 2007 book, From Realism to Real…Read more
  •  55
    Normative Science?
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (3): 310-334. 2012.
    This article revises a paper I read at the SAAP session in honor of my late friend, Richard Robin. The discussion that followed the paper was much better than the paper, and my present effort, I hope, has benefited from that discussion. What I say here is exploratory. I am more confident of my criticisms of other authors than of the alternative I propose. It is the mere sketch of an idea, its many obvious difficulties blithely ignored. I hope in later articles to make up for present deficiencies…Read more
  •  57
    Empiricism Expanded
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 51 (1): 1. 2015.
    Two aspects of Peirce’s mature philosophy seem to me not to have been sufficiently appreciated. They are its empiricist method and its continuity with his scientific research. The research led to and justified the method.1Ground must be cleared before we can proceed. Simplistic ideas of the empirical must be swept aside and Peirce’s empiricism accurately identified. We must also distinguish two theories of meaning that have been associated with empiricist philosophies and show that Peirce combin…Read more
  •  109
    Did Peirce Have a Cosmology?
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 46 (4): 521-543. 2010.
    W. B. Gallie's words about Peirce's cosmology—"the black sheep or white elephant of his philosophical progeny" (1952, p. 216)—have often been quoted, usually as a preface to giving a better account of the animal. That he attributed the view to 'contemporary philosophers' and did not assert it himself has usually been ignored. True, Gallie did argue that the "cosmology is a failure, and an inevitable failure" (p. 236), but he also said that Peirce himself "recognized … that his work in this field…Read more
  •  11
    On a Mistaken Emendation of Peirce's 1903 Harvard Lectures
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 57 (3): 341-352. 2022.
    ARRAY
  •  16
    Robin on Perception and Sentiment in Peirce
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 38 (1/2). 2002.
  •  108
    Darwin's concept of final cause: Neither new nor trivial (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 17 (3): 323-340. 2002.
    Darwin'suse of final cause accords with the Aristotelian idea of finalcauses as explanatory types – as opposed to mechanical causes, which arealways particulars. In Wright's consequence etiology, anadaptation is explained by particular events, namely, its past consequences;hence, that etiology is mechanistic at bottom. This justifies Ghiselin'scharge that such versions of teleology trivialize the subject, But a purelymechanistic explanation of an adaptation allows it to appear coincidental.Patte…Read more