•  6
    Praise, objective rightness and extended action
    Synthese 202 (6): 1-15. 2023.
    There’s more to meriting praise than doing what’s objectively right. After all, one might do what’s objectively right as the result of a fluke or with malicious intent. While doing what’s objectively right is not enough to merit praise, it’s natural to think that some list of sufficient conditions can be assembled. The most common approach to such lists entails that, when one does what is objectively right with the appropriate epistemic state and/or motivation, one merits praise for one’s action…Read more
  •  42
    Procedural chances and the equality of claims
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (2): 324-343. 2021.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
  •  35
    The Case against Unanimous Jury Requirements
    Journal of Political Philosophy 31 (1): 24-41. 2022.
    Journal of Political Philosophy, EarlyView.
  •  32
    Here, there, or delaware? How corporate threats distort democracy
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 22 (1): 55-75. 2023.
    Concern for corporate influence on democratic decisions has mostly focused on campaign funding and access to legislators. While these are certainly worrisome, corporations have another tool to influence decisions, which they are increasingly using. They can threaten to move their operations or cancel expansion plans in a municipality unless its public officials pass (or kill) certain policies. In one sense, this is business as usual. Companies have the right to decide where to operate, and it is…Read more
  •  38
    The Wrong Understanding of Praise
    Erkenntnis 88 (4): 1643-1660. 2023.
    It’s widely accepted that whether or not an agent merits praise for performing a particular action importantly depends on her motivation in doing so. What has received less attention is the importance of an agent’s moral understanding to whether she merits praise for performing a particular action, or whether her action has ‘moral worth.’ The first task of this paper is relatively straightforward: to show that two prominent attempts to address the importance of moral understanding to moral worth…Read more
  •  13
    The Enactivist Self- Virtual or Autonomous?
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 22 (7-8): 183-200. 2015.
    In his foundational enactivist writings, Francisco Varela explained the self as 'virtual', 'fictional', and 'groundless'. More recent enactivist scholars have taken issue with Varela's analysis, elevating the self to the same ontological status as other biological processes. On their interpretation, our 'self' can be considered an autonomous system in the same manner as cells, organs, and organisms. After discussing the enactivist's definition of an autonomous system, this paper examines the lac…Read more
  •  69
    When Manipulation Gets Personal
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (3): 464-478. 2016.
    Many accounts of moral responsibility have emerged recently that question the importance of conscious choice for moral responsibility. Instead of this ‘volitional’ requirement, these ‘attributionist’ accounts claim that agents are responsible for their actions when their actions reflect who they are and what they value. This paper argues that attributionist accounts are too quick to dismiss the connection between volition and moral responsibility. By excising conscious control from their account…Read more
  •  18
    Two faces of rationality
    Synthese 198 (11): 11103-11124. 2020.
    In this paper, I present a puzzle about the connection between an agent’s knowledge and her rationality and a way to solve it. The puzzle is that, intuitively, many of us want to accept both that it is rational for an agent to act on what she knows and that it is irrational for an agent to take what she knows for granting in her practical reasoning. These two claims about rationality present us with a puzzle because, holding fixed our interpretation of rationality, we cannot accept them both. Ac…Read more
  •  17
    Utility Monsters and the Distribution of Dharmas: A Reply to Charles Goodman
    Philosophy East and West 66 (2): 650-652. 2016.
    In both the Consequences of Compassion and his response to my article, Goodman outlines a consequentialist theory that is both coherent and, in many ways, compelling. One can imagine that out of a concern toward—as Goodman puts it—“the impersonal events which fill the world”, we will accept “momentary experiences as the morally significant units”, and our actions will aim to promote the existence of “good dharmas.” However, as this brief reply argues, Goodman’s equating of a consequentialism foc…Read more
  •  24
    Selfless Ethics: The Equality of Non-Existence
    Philosophy East and West 66 (2): 627-637. 2016.
    A number of scholars have attempted to situate the Buddha’s teachings within the primary Western ethical theories, namely consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. One challenge that each has confronted is Buddhism’s emphasis on the ultimate non-existence of the self. In his writings, Charles Goodman has put forward an account of how the realization of the ultimate non-existence of the self would lead a practitioner to consequentialism. The present comment challenges the account offered b…Read more
  •  17
    There is an emerging consensus that human behavior is governed by two types of processes: System 1 processes, which are quicker, automatic, and run in parallel, and System 2 processes, which are slower, more conscious, and run in serial. Among such “dual-process” theorists, however, there is disagreement about whether the premises we use in our conscious, S2 reasoning should be considered as beliefs. In this exchange, one facet that has been largely overlooked is how conscious beliefs are struct…Read more
  •  19
    From conscious experience to a conscious self
    Philosophical Psychology 29 (3): 419-431. 2016.
    In his book The Opacity of Mind, Peter Carruthers presents the Interpretive Sensory Awareness theory, which holds that while we have direct access to our own sensory states, our access to “self-knowledge” is almost always interpretive. In presenting his view, Carruthers also claims that his account is the first of its kind; after a cursory examination of major theories of mind, he concludes that “transparent access” accounts of self-knowledge—the alternative to ISA—have been endorsed throughout …Read more
  •  65
    Rational Action and Moral Ownership
    Neuroethics 7 (2): 195-203. 2013.
    In exploring the impact of cognitive science findings on compatibilist theories of moral responsibility such as Fischer and Ravizza’s, most attention has focused on whether agents are, in fact, responsive to reasons. In doing so, however, we have largely ignored our improved understanding of agents’ epistemic access to their reasons for acting. The “ownership” component of Fischer and Ravizza’s theory depends on agents being able to see the causal efficacy of their conscious deliberation. Cognit…Read more
  •  74
    Statistical evidence and incentives in the law
    Philosophical Issues 31 (1): 128-145. 2021.
    Philosophical Issues, Volume 31, Issue 1, Page 128-145, October 2021.