•  3177
    No Self?: A Look at a Buddhist Argument
    International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (4): 453-466. 2002.
    Central to Buddhist thought and practice is the anattā doctrine. In its unrestricted form the doctrine amounts to the claim that nothing at all possesses self-nature. This article examines an early Buddhist argument for the doctrine. The argument, roughly, is that (i) if anything were a self, it would be both unchanging and self-determining; (ii) nothing has both of these properties; therefore, (iii) nothing is a self. The thesis of this article is that, despite the appearance of formal validity…Read more
  •  922
    From Democrat to Dissident
    In T. Allan Hillman & Tully Borland (eds.), Dissident Philosophers: Voices Against the Political Current of the Academy, Rowman and Littlefield. pp. 261-277. 2022.
    Recounts the author's experiences and reasons that led him to reject the Democratic Party and become a conservative.
  •  493
    Can the Chariot Take Us to the Land of No Self?
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 9 29-33. 2006.
    This paper examines a famous argument for the Buddhist doctrine of anatta ("no self) according to which nothing possesses self-nature or substantial reality. The argument unfolds during a debate between the monk Nagasena and King Milinda (Menandros). Nagasena's challenge to the King is that he demonstrate the substantial reality of the chariot in which he arrived at their meeting when said chariot is (i) not identical to any one of its proper parts, (ii) not identical to the mereological sum of …Read more
  •  472
    Van Inwagen on Fiction, Existence, Properties, Particulars, and Method
    Studia Neoaristotelica 12 (2): 99-125. 2015.
    This paper is a review of the book "Existence: Essays in Ontology" by Peter Van Inwagen.
  •  378
  •  366
    Hugh McCann on the Implications of Divine Sovereignty
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1): 149-161. 2014.
    This review article summarizes and in part criticizes Hugh J. McCann’s detailed elaboration of the consequences of the idea that God is absolutely sovereign and thus unlimited in knowledge and power in his 2012 Creation and the Sovereignty of God. While there is much to agree with in McCann’s treatment, it is argued that divine sovereignty cannot extend as far as he would like to extend it. The absolute lord of the natural and moral orders cannot be absolutely sovereign over the conceptual and m…Read more
  •  286
    Does the Cosmological Argument Depend on the Ontological?
    Faith and Philosophy 17 (4): 441-458. 2000.
    Does the cosmological argument (CA) depend on the ontological (OA)? That depends. If the OA is an argument “from mere concepts,” then no; if the OA is an argument from possibility, then yes. That is my main thesis. Along the way, I explore a number of subsidiary themes, among them, the nature of proof in metaphysics, and what Kant calls the “mystery of absolute necessity.”
  •  280
    Divine Simplicity
    Faith and Philosophy 9 (4): 508-525. 1992.
    The doctrine of divine simplicity, according to which God is devoid of physical or metaphysical complexity, is widely believed to be incoherent. I argue that although two prominent recent attempts to defend it fail, it can be defended against the charge of obvious incoherence. The defense rests on the isolation and rejection of a crucial assumption, namely, that no property is an individual. I argue that there is nothing in our ordinary concepts of property and individual to warrant the assum…Read more
  •  279
    Butchvarov on the Dehumanization of Philosophy
    Studia Neoaristotelica 13 (2): 181-196. 2016.
    This review article examines Panayot Butchvarov’s claim that philosophy in its three main branches, epistemology, ethics, and metaphysics, needs to be freed from anthropocentrism.
  •  251
    From facts to God: An onto-cosmological argument (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48 (3): 157-181. 2000.
  •  197
    This article examines one of the sources of David Benatar’s anti-natalism. This is the view that ‘all procreation is [morally] wrong.’ (Benatar and Wasserman, 2015:12) One of its sources is the claim that each of our lives is objectively bad, hence bad whether we think so or not. The question I will pose is whether the constraints of metaphysical naturalism allow for an objective devaluation of human life sufficiently negative to justify anti-natalism. My thesis is that metaphysical naturalism d…Read more
  •  178
    This article articulates and defends F. H. Bradley's regress argument against external relations using contemporary analytic techniques and conceptuality. Bradley's argument is usually quickly dismissed as if it were beneath serious consideration. But I shall maintain that Bradley's argument, suitably reconstructed, is a powerful argument, plausibly premised, and free of such obvious fallacies as petitio principii. Thus it does not rest on the question‐begging assumption that all relations are i…Read more
  •  159
    Divine Simplicity
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2019.
  •  159
    This review article explores in a critical spirit the differences between constituent and relational ontology as practiced by four contemporary Aristotelian philosophers, Michael J. Loux, E. J. Lowe, Lukáš Novák, and Stanislav Sousedík
  •  157
    God, causation and occasionalism
    Religious Studies 35 (1): 3-18. 1999.
    The doctrine that there are no logically necessary connections in nature can be used to support both occasionalism, according to which God alone can be a cause, and 'anti-occasionalism', according to which God cannot be a cause. Quentin Smith has recently invoked the 'no logically necessary connections in nature' doctrine in support of the latter. I bring two main objections against his thesis that God (logically) cannot be a cause. The first is that there are good reasons to think that there ar…Read more
  •  156
    The Hume-Edwards Objection to the Cosmological Argument
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 423-443. 1997.
    One sort of cosmological argument for the existence of God starts from the fact that the universe exists and argues to a transcendent cause of this fact. According to the Hume-Edwards objection to this sort of cosmological argument, if every member of the universe is caused by a preceding member, then the universe has an intemal causal explanation in such a way as to obviate the need for a transcendent cause. The Hume-Edwards objection has recently come under attack by atheists and theists alike…Read more
  •  146
    Could the universe cause itself to exist?
    Philosophy 75 (4): 604-612. 2000.
    This article responds to Quentin Smith's, ‘The Reason the Universe Exists is that it Caused Itself to Exist’, Philosophy 74 (1999), 579–586. My rejoinder makes three main points. The first is that Smith's argument for a finitely old, but causally self-explanatory, universe fails from probative overkill: if sound, it also shows that all manner of paltry event-sequences are causally self-explanatory.The second point is that the refutation of Smith's argument extends to Hume's argument for an infin…Read more
  •  113
  •  108
    Kant, Heidegger, and the Problem of the Thing in Itself
    International Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1): 35-43. 1983.
  •  106
    A Tension in Quine’s Theory of Existence
    Philo 6 (2): 193-204. 2003.
    According to Quine, the ontological question can be posed in three Anglo-Saxon monosyllables: “What is there?” But if we call this the ontological question, what shall we call the logically prior question: “What is it for an item to be there?” Peter van Inwagen has recently suggested that this be called the meta-ontological question, and more importantly, has endorsed Quine’s answer to it. Ingredient in this Quinean answer to the meta-ontological question are several theses, among them, “Being i…Read more
  •  95
    Bradley’s Regress and Relation-Instances
    Modern Schoolman 81 (3): 159-183. 2004.
  •  92
    Incarnation and Identity
    Philo 5 (1): 84-93. 2002.
    The characteristic claim of Christianity, as codified at Chalcedon, is that God the Son, the second person of the Trinity, is numerically the same person as Jesus of Nazareth. This article raises three questions that appear to threaten the coherence of orthodox Chalcedonian incarnationalism. First, how can one person exemplify seemingly incompatible natures? Second, how can one person exemplify seemingly incompatible non-nature properties? Third, how can there be one person if the concept of inc…Read more
  •  89
    Has the Ontological Argument Been Refuted?
    Religious Studies 29 (1). 1993.
    Suppose we say that a deductive argument is probative just in case it is valid in point of logical form, possesses true premises, and is free of informal fallacy. We can then say that an argument is normatively persuasive for a person if and only if it is both probative and has premises that can be accepted, without any breach of epistemic propriety, by the person in question. If the premises of a probative argument would be accepted by any reasonable person, I will call such an argument demonst…Read more
  •  84
    Could a Classical Theist Be a Physicalist?
    Faith and Philosophy 15 (2): 160-180. 1998.
    Since physicalism is fashionable nowadays, one should perhaps not be too surprised to find a growing number of theistic philosophers bent on combining theism with physicalism. I shall be arguing that this is an innovation we have good reason to resist. I begin by distinguishing global physicalism (physicalism about everything) from local physicalism (physicalism about human beings). I then present the theist who would be a physicalist with a challenge: Articulate a version of local physicalism t…Read more