•  1
    Responsibility and Respect
    In Carl Knight & Zofia Stemplowska (eds.), Responsibility and Distributive Justice, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 115--35. 2011.
  •  26
    This book honours David Miller's remarkable contribution to political philosophy. Over the last fifty years, Miller has published an extraordinary range of work that has shaped the discipline in many different areas, including social justice, democracy, citizenship, nationality, global justice, and the history of political thought. His work is characterised by its commitment to a kind of theorising that makes sense to the people who have to put its principles into practice. This entails paying c…Read more
  •  59
  •  14
    Non‐ideal Theory
    In Kasper Lippert‐Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee & David Coady (eds.), A Companion to Applied Philosophy, Wiley. 2016.
    The two main questions addressed in the chapter are “What is the point of (good) nonideal theory?” and “Can (good) nonideal theory be done in isolation from ideal theory?” To address them, I distinguish between different types of nonideal theory and locate nonideal theory vis‐à‐vis ideal theory as well as realism and applied philosophy. I argue that nonideal theory is useful but some of its versions need to concede that they are defeatist. I also argue that nonideal theory builds on ideal theory…Read more
  •  11
    Rawls on Ideal and Nonideal Theory
    with Adam Swift
    In Jon Mandle & David A. Reidy (eds.), A Companion to Rawls, Wiley-blackwell. 2013.
    John Rawls tells at the start of A Theory of Justice that his theory is intentionally constrained in two ways: it is ideal and focuses on the justice of the basic structure of society. This chapter begins by evaluating Rawls's claim that ideal theory sets the target of reform for nonideal theory, whose task it is to work out what to do “under less happy conditions.” It states that it is unclear just when ideal theory can inform the priorities of nonideal theory. The chapter also presents discuss…Read more
  •  4
    Substantive Responsibility and the Causal Thesis
    In Markus Stepanians & Michael Frauchiger (eds.), Reason, Justification, and Contractualism: Themes from Scanlon, De Gruyter. pp. 119-130. 2021.
  •  1
    Can moral desert qualify or justify human rights?
    In Rowan Cruft, S. Matthew Liao & Massimo Renzo (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, Oxford University Press Uk. 2015.
  •  16
    ‘Go Tell the Spartans, Passerby’: Whom to Remember Ahead of Whom?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (5): 825-840. 2022.
    The dead are among us. We are reminded of their names through the books we read, the hoovers we buy, the sandwiches we consume, the tarmac we travel on, the wellingtons we wear, or, frequently, the buildings we visit. Even if we settled on the criteria for being worthy of commemoration, what should we do about the fact that there seem to be so many people who would likely meet them? Commemoration is a form of attention giving, and attention is a scarce resource. It is scarce even if it could be …Read more
  •  22
    ‘Go Tell the Spartans, Passerby’: Whom to Remember Ahead of Whom?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (5): 825-840. 2022.
    The dead are among us. We are reminded of their names through the books we read, the hoovers we buy, the sandwiches we consume, the tarmac we travel on, the wellingtons we wear, or, frequently, the buildings we visit. Even if we settled on the criteria for being worthy of commemoration, what should we do about the fact that there seem to be so many people who would likely meet them? Commemoration is a form of attention giving, and attention is a scarce resource. It is scarce even if it could be …Read more
  •  21
    Citizens with Benefits
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 96 (1): 41-58. 2022.
    Can states permissibly enforce mandatory participation in the provision of public goods? Usual justifications of state action here appeal to the fact that such goods are very good for people. Arthur Ripstein argues that states can compel provision of public goods, but that the best explanation of this is grounded, not in the costs and benefits of the provision to the compelled parties, but in the parties’ moral status as independent agents. I argue that Ripstein’s alternative account poses more …Read more
  •  18
    Is Humanity under a Duty to Deliver Socioeconomic Human Rights?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (2): 202-211. 2021.
    What’s special about human rights? For Rowan Cruft human rights are special because they capture the importance of the good of the right-holder. But his account struggles with explaining the existence of global socioeconomic human rights. I argue that such rights exist and show how we should revise Cruft’s account to accommodate this.
  •  232
    Responsibility and distributive justice (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Under what conditions are people responsible for their choices and the outcomes of those choices? How could such conditions be fostered by liberal societies? Should what people are due as a matter of justice depend on what they are responsible for? For example, how far should healthcare provision depend on patients' past choices? What values would be realized and which hampered by making justice sensitive to responsibility? Would it give people what they deserve? Would it advance or hinder equal…Read more
  •  41
    Is Humanity under a Duty to Deliver Socioeconomic Human Rights?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (2): 202-211. 2021.
    What’s special about human rights? For Rowan Cruft human rights are special because they capture the importance of the good of the right-holder. But his account struggles with explaining the existence of global socioeconomic human rights. I argue that such rights exist and show how we should revise Cruft’s account to accommodate this.
  •  43
    The incentives account of feasibility
    Philosophical Studies 178 (7): 2385-2401. 2020.
    In Utopophobia Estlund offers a prominent version of a conditional account of feasibility. I think the account is too permissive. I defend an alternative incentives account of feasibility. The incentives account preserves the spirit of the conditional account but qualifies fewer actions as feasible. Simplified, the account holds that an action is feasible if there is an incentive such that, given the incentive, the agent is likely to perform the action successfully. If we accept that ought impli…Read more
  •  22
    Coercing Compliers to Do More Than One’s Fair Share
    Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 2 (1): 147-160. 2019.
    Is there a duty to do more than one’s fair share of solving collective problems? If there is, can those who do less than their fair share coerce others to do more? These questions arise urgently in relation to the problem of refugee protection. The fact that various states host refugees to a dramatically different extent is due to a range of factors but the most prominent one is that, on the whole, states devote their differential capabilities to the aim of not hosting them. When some states fai…Read more
  •  1
    Responsibility and Respect: Reconciling Two Egalitarian Visions
    In Carl Knight & Zofia Stemplowska (eds.), Responsibility and Distributive Justice, Oxford University Press Uk. 2011.
  •  59
    Feasibility: Individual and collective
    Social Philosophy and Policy 33 (1-2): 273-291. 2016.
  •  26
    Remembering War: Fabre on Remembrance
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 36 (3): 382-390. 2018.
    Following wars, what requirements, if any, of remembrance do we – those who live in peacetime – have? On whom do they fall? Who must be remembered? How should they be remembered? Fabre offers us an account of remembrance that answers some of those questions and provides a helpful framework for working through the others. It is philosophically nuanced as well as attuned to the complexity of war and informed by actual commemorative practices. In this article, however, I expand Fabre's list of desi…Read more
  •  44
    How generous should egalitarians be?
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 22 (3): 269-283. 2019.
  •  95
    Doing more than one’s fair share
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (5): 591-608. 2016.
  •  135
    Rescuing Luck Egalitarianism
    Journal of Social Philosophy 44 (4): 402-419. 2013.
  •  163
    Harmful Choices: Scanlon and Voorhoeve on Substantive Responsibility
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (4): 1-488. 2013.
    How should the fact that a given policy offers people choice bear on policy selection? Should we favour choice-granting policies even if choices lead to harmful outcomes, and even if the causal thesis is true and people are not fully in control of how they choose? T.M. Scanlon and Alex Voorhoeve have tried to locate the significance of choice in the value or potential value that it has for choice-bearers. I show that this leaves them vulnerable to a general dilemma: either they can explain the s…Read more
  •  17
    Sen's Modest Justice
    Jurisprudence 5 (2): 376-384. 2014.
  •  136
    Holding people responsible for what they do not control
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 7 (4): 355-377. 2008.
    A crucial question for egalitarians, and theorists of distributive justice in general, is whether people can be held responsible for disadvantages they bring upon themselves. One response to this question states that it would be inegalitarian to hold people responsible on the basis of their actions if their actions are not ultimately under their control and reflect instead the good or bad luck the agent had in being the type of person who happens to act in a given way. I argue that even if we ac…Read more
  •  41
    Dignified Morality
    with Matthew Clayton
    Jurisprudence 6 (2): 309-326. 2015.
  •  359
    What’s Ideal About Ideal Theory?
    Social Theory and Practice 34 (3): 319-340. 2008.
  • Brill Online Books and Journals
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 10 (4). 2013.