•  442
    A (Different) Virtue Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1): 1-26. 2012.
    Section 1 articulates a genus-species claim: that knowledge is a kind of success from ability. Equivalently: In cases of knowledge, S’s success in believing the truth is attributable to S’s ability. That idea is then applied to questions about the nature and value of knowledge. Section 2 asks what it would take to turn the genus-species claim into a proper theory of knowledge; that is, into informative, necessary and sufficient conditions. That question is raised in the context of an important l…Read more
  •  381
    Knowledge and success from ability
    Philosophical Studies 142 (1). 2009.
    This paper argues that knowledge is an instance of a more general and familiar normative kind—that of success through ability (or success through excellence, or success through virtue). This thesis is developed in the context of three themes prominent in the recent literature: that knowledge attributions are somehow context sensitive; that knowledge is intimately related to practical reasoning; and that one purpose of the concept of knowledge is to flag good sources of information. Wedding these…Read more
  •  90
    The Force of Hume’s Skepticism About Unobserved Matters of Fact
    Journal of Philosophical Research 23 289-306. 1998.
    According to a popular objection, Hume assumes that only deductive inferences can generate knowledge and reasonable belief, and so Hume’s skepticism can be avoided by simply recognizing the role of inductive inferences in empirical matters. This paper offers an interpretation of Hume’s skepticism that avoids this objection. The resulting skeptical argument is a powerful one in the following sense: it is not at all obvious where the argument goes wrong, and responding to the argument forces us to…Read more
  •  354
    External world skepticism
    Philosophy Compass 2 (4). 2007.
    Recent literature in epistemology has focused on the following argument for skepticism (SA): I know that I have two hands only if I know that I am not a handless brain in a vat. But I don't know I am not a handless brain in a vat. Therefore, I don't know that I have two hands. Part I of this article reviews two responses to skepticism that emerged in the 1980s and 1990s: sensitivity theories and attributor contextualism. Part II considers the more recent ‘neo-Moorean’ response to skepticism and …Read more
  • Skepticism and the Modern Ontology
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 73 217-228. 1999.
  •  54
    Scepticism and Epistemic Kinds
    Noûs 34 (s1). 2000.
    This paper responds to a claim by Christopher Hookway, that Fumerton’s Principle of Inferential Justification (PIJ) is a platitude, and that skeptical arguments that deploy it depend essentially on a substantive thesis about the nature of epistemic kinds. This paper argues that, contrary to Hookway, the thesis about epistemic kinds is not necessary to generate skeptical results, and PIJ is sufficient to do so.
  •  13
    Evidence and Inquiry (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 36 (2): 231-234. 1996.
  •  28
    Why Not Reliabilism?
    In Olsson Erik (ed.), The Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 31--41. 2003.
  •  68
    Common sense in Thomas Reid
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 142-155. 2011.
    This paper explains the nature and role of common sense in Reid and uses the exposition to answer some of Reid's critics. The key to defending Reid is to distinguish between two kinds of priority that common sense beliefs are supposed to enjoy. Common sense beliefs enjoy epistemological priority in that they constitute a foundation for knowledge; i.e. they have evidential status without being grounded in further evidence themselves. Common sense beliefs enjoy methodological priority in that they…Read more
  •  18
    Religious Knowledge in the Context of Conflicting Testimony
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 83 61-76. 2009.
    An adequate account of testimonial knowledge in general explains how religious knowledge can be grounded in testimony, and even in the context of conflicting testimonial traditions. Three emerging trends in epistemology help to make that case. The first is to make a distinction between two projects of epistemology: “the project of explanation” and “the project of vindication.” The second is to emphasize a distinction between knowledge and understanding. The third is to ask what role the concept …Read more
  •  40
    22. virtues in epistemology
    In Steven Luper (ed.), Essential Knowledge: Readings in Epistemology, Longman. pp. 211. 2003.
    In ”Virtues in Epistemology,” John Greco presents and evaluates two main notions of intellectual virtue. The first concerns Ernest Sosa's development of this concept as a disposition to grasp truth and avoid falsehood. Greco contrasts this with moral models of intellectual virtue that include a motivational component in their definition, namely a desire for truth. Instead, Greco argues that a minimalist reliabilist account of intellectual virtue “in which the virtues are conceived as reliable co…Read more
  • ``Agent Reliabilism"
    In James Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspecives, Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Co.. 1999.
  •  18
    Plantinga, Foundationalism, and the Charge of Self-referential Incoherence
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 31 (1): 187-193. 1988.
    Alvin Plantinga charges classical foundationalism with self-referential incoherence, meaning that that doctrine employs criteria for rationally acceptable propositions which exclude the criteria themselves. More specifically, the charge is that the criteria are neither properly basic nor supported by properly basic propositions. In section 1 the doctrine of classical foundationalism is briefly explained. In section 2, a defense against Plantinga's objection is provided showing how the foundation…Read more
  •  7
    The Value Problem
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Epistemic Value, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 313--22. 2009.
  •  220
    In section one the deontological (or responsibilist) conception of justification is discussed and explained. In section two, arguments are put forward in order to derive the most plausible version of perspectival internalism, or the position that epistemic justification is a function of factors internal to the believer's cognitive perspective. The two most common considerations put forward in favor of perspectival internalism are discussed. These are the responsibilist conception of justificatio…Read more
  •  63
    Skepticism, Reliabilism, and Virtue Epistemology
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5 139-147. 2000.
    I review a familiar skeptical argument from Hume, and conclude that it requires us to accept that there is no necessary relation between beliefs about the world and their evidential grounds; that is, there is no logical or quasi-logical relation between empirical beliefs and their grounds, such that their grounds entail them, or even make them probable. I then argue that generic reliabilism can accommodate this fact about evidential grounds in a non-skeptical way. According to reliabilism, the g…Read more
  •  34
    Epistemic Justification (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 21 (4): 547-549. 2004.
  •  40
    A reply to strouds skeptic
    Philosophical Papers 16 (1): 23-39. 1987.
    No abstract
  •  47
    Evidentialism: Essays in Epistemology
    International Philosophical Quarterly 45 (4): 556-558. 2005.
  •  20
    Scepticism and Epistemic Kinds
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 366-376. 2000.
  •  280
    Worries about Pritchard’s safety
    Synthese 158 (3): 299-302. 2007.
    I take issue with two claims that Duncan Pritchard makes in his recent book, "Epistemic Luck". The first concerns his safety-based response to the lottery problem; the second his account of the relationship between safety and intellectual virtue.
  •  13
    A Virtue Epistemology (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 50 (3): 399-401. 2010.
  •  20
    The second major thesis of the book follows closely on the first: that the analysis of skeptical arguments is philosophically useful and important, and should therefore have a central role in the methodology of philosophy, and especially in the methodology of epistemology. A close analysis of skeptical arguments highlights our pre-theoretically plausible, but ultimately mistaken, assumptions about the nature of knowledge and evidence. Skeptical arguments are powerful just because their assumptio…Read more
  •  130
    A Different Sort of Contextualism
    Erkenntnis 61 (2-3): 383-400. 2004.
    A number of virtue epistemologists endorse the following thesis: Knowledge is true belief resulting from intellectual virtue, where Ss true belief results from intellectual virtue just in case S believes the truth because S is intellectually virtuous. This thesis commits one to a sort of contextualism about knowledge attributions. This is because, in general, sentences of the form X occurred because Y occurred require a contextualist treatment. This sort of contextualism is contrasted with more …Read more
  •  6
    Perception as Interpretation
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 72 229-237. 1998.
  •  360
    The nature of ability and the purpose of knowledge
    Philosophical Issues 17 (1). 2007.
    The claim that knowledge is a kind of success from ability has great theoretical power: it explains the nature of epistemic normativity, why knowledge is incompatible with luck, and why knowledge is more valuable than mere true belief. This paper addresses objections to the view by wedding it with two additional ideas: that intellectual abilities display a certain structure, and that the concept of knowledge functions to flag good information, and good sources of information, for use in practica…Read more