•  95
    Philosophers sometimes approach meaning metaphorically, for example, by speaking of “grasping” meanings, as if understanding consists in getting mental hands around something.1 Philosophers say that a theory of meaning should be a theory about the meanings that people assign to expressions in their language, that to understand other people requires identifying the meanings they associate with what they are saying, and that to translate an expression of another language into your own is to find a…Read more
  •  92
    Justice and Moral Bargaining
    Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (1): 114. 1983.
    INTRODUCTION In my view, justice is entirely conventional; indeed, all of morality consists in conventions that are the result of continual tacit bargaining and adjustment. This is not to say social arrangements are just whenever they are in accordance with the principles of justice accepted in that society. We can use our own principles of justice in judging the institutions of another society, and we can appeal to some principles we accept in order to criticize other principles we accept. To u…Read more
  •  91
    Character
    with Maria Merritt and John Doris
    In John M. Doris (ed.), Moral Psychology Handbook, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  89
    Category mistakes in m&e
    Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1). 2003.
    Theories of causation may imply that your birth causes your death, which seems odd in the way that it is not odd to say that your birth precedes your death. Theories of knowledge may imply that the object of knowledge is the same as the object of belief, although we know but do not believe facts and we can know a proposition without knowing whether it is true
  •  87
    Logical form
    Foundations of Language 9 (1): 38-65. 1972.
    Theories of adverbial modification can be roughly distinguished into two sorts. One kind of theory takes logical form to follow surface grammatical form. Adverbs are treated as unanalyzable logical operators that turn a predicate or sentence into a different predicate or sentence respectively. And new rules of logic are stated for these operators. A different kind of theory does not suppose that logical form must parallel surface grammatical form. It allows that logical form may have more to do …Read more
  •  85
    Practical aspects of theoretical reasoning
    In Piers Rawling & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 45--56. 2004.
    Harman distinguishes between two uses of the term “logic”: as referring either to the theory of implication or to the theory of reasoning, which are quite distinct. His interest here is reasoning: a process that can modify intentions and beliefs. To a first approximation, theoretical reasoning is concerned with what to believe and practical reasoning is concerned with what to intend to do, although it is possible to have practical reasons to believe something. Practical considerations are releva…Read more
  •  82
    How to use propositions
    American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (2): 173-176. 1977.
  •  76
    The Nature of Morality
    with D. Z. Phillips
    Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110): 89. 1977.
  •  75
    What is cognitively accessed?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 505-505. 2007.
    Is Block's issue about accessing an experience or its object? Having certain experiences appears to be incompatible with accessing the experience itself. And any experience of an object accesses that object. Such access either counts as cognitive or does not. Either way, Block's issue seems resolvable without appeal to the scientific considerations he describes
  •  74
    In his elegant discussion, Sripada distinguishes three possible innate bases for aspects of morality: (1) certain specific principles might be innate, (2) a less simple “principles and parameters” model might apply, and (3) innate biases might have have some influence over what morality a person acquires without determining the content of that morality.1 He argues against (1) and (2) and in favor of (3). Without disputing his case for (3) I will try to say why I think that his arguments against …Read more
  •  74
    In _Reliable Reasoning_, Gilbert Harman and Sanjeev Kulkarni -- a philosopher and an engineer -- argue that philosophy and cognitive science can benefit from statistical learning theory, the theory that lies behind recent advances in machine learning. The philosophical problem of induction, for example, is in part about the reliability of inductive reasoning, where the reliability of a method is measured by its statistically expected percentage of errors -- a central topic in SLT. After discussi…Read more
  •  74
    The Nonexistence of Character Traits
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (2): 223-226. 2000.
  •  73
    Moral Relativism as a Foundation for Natural Rights
    Journal of Libertarian Studies 4 (4): 367-371. 1980.
  •  72
    Inferential justification
    Journal of Philosophy 73 (17): 570-571. 1976.
  •  72
    Love isn't all you need (review)
    Times Literary Supplement 26 (5104): 26. 2001.
    Virtue ethics is a type of ethical theory in which the notion of virtue or good character plays a central role. This splendid new book describes a “program” for the development of a particular (“Aristotelian”) form of virtue ethics. The book is intended to be used as a textbook, but should be read by anyone interested in moral philosophy. Hursthouse has been a major contributor to the development of virtue ethics and the program she describes, while making use of the many contributions of others…Read more
  •  71
    Review of Ernest Lepore and Kirk Ludwig, Donald Davidson's Truth-Theoretic Semantics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (3): 788-792. 2010.
  •  70
    Reasoning and Evidence One Does Not Possess1
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1): 163-182. 1980.
  •  66
    Stringency of Rights and "Ought"The Realm of Rights.Fundamental Legal Conceptions
    with Judith Jarvis Thomson, Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, and Walter Wheeler Cook
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (1): 181. 1993.
  •  66
    Statistical Learning Theory: A Tutorial
    with Sanjeev R. Kulkarni
    Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Computational Statistics 3 (6): 543-556. 2011.
    In this article, we provide a tutorial overview of some aspects of statistical learning theory, which also goes by other names such as statistical pattern recognition, nonparametric classification and estimation, and supervised learning. We focus on the problem of two-class pattern classification for various reasons. This problem is rich enough to capture many of the interesting aspects that are present in the cases of more than two classes and in the problem of estimation, and many of the resul…Read more
  •  66
    General foundations versus rational insight (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3). 2001.
    BonJour offers two main reasons for supposing that there is such a thing as rational insight into necessity. First, he says there are many examples in which it clearly seems that one has such insight. Second, he argues that any epistemology denying the existence of rational insight into necessity is committed to a narrow skepticism. After commenting about possible frameworks for epistemological justification, I argue against these two claims in reverse order.
  •  64
    Statistical Learning Theory (e.g., Hastie et al., 2001; Vapnik, 1998, 2000, 2006) is the basic theory behind contemporary machine learning and data-mining. We suggest that the theory provides an excellent framework for philosophical thinking about inductive inference.
  •  62
    Rationality in Agreement
    Social Philosophy and Policy 5 (2): 1. 1988.
    Gauthier's title is potentially misleading. The phrase “morals by agreement” suggests a social contract theory of morality according to which basic moral principles arise out of an actual or hypothetical agreement. John Rawls defends a hypothetical agreement version, arguing that the basic principles of justice are those that would be agreed to in an initial position of fair equality. I myself defend an actual agreement version, arguing that the moral principles that apply to a person derive fro…Read more
  •  62
    The most basic theme in Davidson’s writings in philosophy of language in the 1960s is that we are finite beings whose mastery of the indefinitely many expressions of our language must somehow arise out of our mastery of finite resources. Otherwise, there would be an unbounded number of distinct things to learn in learning a language, which would make language learning..
  •  61
    Peacocke argues that all epistemic entitlements depend at bottom on a priori entitlements, determined by "constitutive conditions" for the application of concepts. He does not address familiar doubts about the distinction between constitutive and nonconstitutive conditions of application. In addition, Peacocke conflates issues about inference with issues about implication and proof and seriously misrepresents David Lewis' view about the content of indicative conditionals.