•  34
  •  162
    How to boil a live frog
    Analysis 60 (2). 2000.
  •  873
    The Barber, Russell's Paradox, Catch-22, God, Contradiction, and More
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction, Clarendon Press. pp. 295--313. 2004.
    outrageous remarks about contradictions. Perhaps the most striking remark he makes is that they are not false. This claim first appears in his early notebooks (Wittgenstein 1960, p.108). In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein argued that contradictions (like tautologies) are not statements (Sätze) and hence are not false (or true). This is a consequence of his theory that genuine statements are pictures.
  •  11
    I was commissioned by Barry Smith, Editor of The Monist , to act as Advisory Editor for issue 88.1, January 2005 on the topic Humor, and we drafted the appended description. The deadline for submissions is January 31, 2004, and you are welcome to submit an article to me for consideration (word limit 7,500 words, including footnotes). What the Editor and I are, hoping for, is some serious and seriously good philosophical writing on this topic.
  •  9
    Introduction
    The Monist 88 (1): 3-10. 2005.
    According to some commentators, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus is all one big joke: we plough through the text trying to extract the sense out of each spare and heroic proposition, only to be told at the end, that anyone who understands the author will realize that all of his propositions are nonsensical and so are not even propositions. The whole work is a kind of hoax; the readers are ridiculed, but, with luck, will eventually have to laugh when they come to recognize that what they had taken for de…Read more
  •  25
    Unassertion
    Philosophia 18 (1): 119-121. 1988.
  •  40
    Categories of linguistic aspects and grelling's paradox
    Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (3). 1980.
  •  34
    Paradoxes: Their roots, range and resolution
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4). 2004.
    Book Information Paradoxes: Their Roots, Range and Resolution. Paradoxes: Their Roots, Range and Resolution Nicholas Rescher , Chicago and La Salle : Open Court , 2001 , xxiii + 293 , US$24.95 ( paper ). By Nicholas Rescher. Open Court. Chicago and La Salle. Pp. xxiii + 293. US$24.95 (paper:).
  •  54
    The sorites as a lesson in semantics
    Mind 97 (387): 447-455. 1988.
  •  179
    A consistent way with paradox
    Philosophical Studies 144 (3). 2009.
    Consideration of a paradox originally discovered by John Buridan provides a springboard for a general solution to paradoxes within the Liar family. The solution rests on a philosophical defence of truth-value-gaps and is consistent (non-dialetheist), avoids ‘revenge’ problems, imports no ad hoc assumptions, is not applicable to only a proper subset of the semantic paradoxes and implies no restriction of the expressive capacities of language.
  •  19
    On failing to assert: Reply to David Sherry
    Philosophia 31 (3-4): 579-588. 2004.
  •  34
    To Let: Unsuccessful Stipulation, Bad Proof, and Paradox
    American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (1): 93. 2013.
    Letting is a common practice in mathematics. For example, we let x be the sum of the first n integers and, after a short proof, conclude that x = n(n+1)/2; we let J be the point where the bisectors of two of the angles of a triangle intersect and prove that this coincides with H, the point at which another pair of bisectors of the angles of that triangle intersect. Karl Weierstrass's colleagues, in an attempt to solve optimization problems, stipulated that the minimum area for a triangle with a …Read more
  •  11
    III-A Unified Solution to Some Paradoxes
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1): 53-74. 2000.
  •  129
    Review: Wittgenstein: Meaning and Judgement (review)
    Mind 115 (458): 437-439. 2006.
  •  10
    Humor and Harm
    Sorites 3 27-42. 1995.
    For familiar reasons, stereotyping is believed to be irresponsible and offensive. Yet the use of stereotypes in humor is widespread. Particularly offensive are thought to be sexual and racial stereotypes, yet it is just these that figure particularly prominently in jokes. In certain circumstances it is unquestionably wrong to make jokes that employ such stereotypes. Some writers have made the much stronger claim that in all circumstances it is wrong to find such jokes funny; in other words that …Read more
  •  23
  •  22
    Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics
    Philosophical Quarterly 27 (109): 370. 1977.
  •  71
    Epimenides and Curry
    Analysis 46 (3). 1986.
  •  66
    The title of this paper is 'quotation'
    Analysis 45 (3): 137-140. 1985.
  •  11
    Brevity (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2013.
    Brevity in conversation is a window to the workings of the mind. It is both a multifaceted topic of deep philosophical importance and a phenomenon that serves as a testing ground for theories in linguistics, psycholinguistics and computer modeling. Speakers use elliptical constructions and exploit salient features of the conversational environment, a process of pragmatic enrichment, so as to pack a great deal into a few words. They also tailor their words to theirparticular conversational partne…Read more
  •  8
    Goldstein invites the philosophical beginner to think hard about issues ranging from patriotism and racism to artificial intelligence and the mind, from love and fidelity to free will and mortality, taking an interdisciplinary approach.
  •  98
    Introduction
    The Monist 88 (1): 3-10. 2005.
    According to some commentators, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus is all one big joke: we plough through the text trying to extract the sense out of each spare and heroic proposition, only to be told at the end, that anyone who understands the author will realize that all of his propositions are nonsensical and so are not even propositions. The whole work is a kind of hoax; the readers are ridiculed, but, with luck, will eventually have to laugh when they come to recognize that what they had taken for de…Read more
  •  43
    The Form of The Third Man Argument
    with Paul Mannick
    Apeiron 12 (2). 1978.
    Our interpretation of the "parmenides" 132a1 - 132b2 has the following features. (i) it stresses that the third man argument is an infinite regress and (ii) notes its epistemological thrust. (iii) a faithful translation of the last line of the argument reads "and no longer will each of the forms be for you one but each is infinite in multitude." parmenides' point is that each form, which socrates believed to be complete (one), turns out to be an unbounded, incompletable series of subforms useles…Read more
  •  18
    Smooth and Rough Logic
    Philosophical Investigations 15 (2): 93-110. 1992.
  •  106
    False stipulation and semantical paradox
    Analysis 46 (4): 192-195. 1986.
  •  34
    Strengthened paradoxes
    with Leonard Goddard
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (3). 1980.
    This Article does not have an abstract