•  60
    Farewell to grelling
    Analysis 63 (1). 2003.
  •  54
    The sorites as a lesson in semantics
    Mind 97 (387): 447-455. 1988.
  •  49
    III A Unified Solution to Some Paradoxes
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (n/a): 53-74. 2000.
    The Russell class does not exist because the conditions purporting to specify that class are contradictory, and hence fail to specify any class. Equally, the conditions purporting to specify the Liar statement are contradictory and hence, although the Liar sentence is grammatically in order, it fails to yield a statement. Thus the common source of these and related paradoxes is contradictory (or tautologous) specifying conditions-for such conditions fail to specify. This is the diagnosis. The cu…Read more
  •  45
    Pure Categorial Principles
    The Monist 66 (3): 410-421. 1983.
    If nowadays categories seems to cover a multitude of different enquiries, we can see some continuity and coherence among them, and we can get some sense of what the subject is, by going back to the first treatise to receive the name, the Categories of Aristotle. The scheme of categories worked out by Aristotle in that book was used by him in subsequent works to solve a variety of problems. On one plausible hypothesis, Aristotle’s scheme was partly shaped by ontological considerations. However, o…Read more
  •  44
    Drawing hands
    The Philosophers' Magazine 45 (45): 79-79. 2009.
  •  43
    The Form of The Third Man Argument
    with Paul Mannick
    Apeiron 12 (2). 1978.
    Our interpretation of the "parmenides" 132a1 - 132b2 has the following features. (i) it stresses that the third man argument is an infinite regress and (ii) notes its epistemological thrust. (iii) a faithful translation of the last line of the argument reads "and no longer will each of the forms be for you one but each is infinite in multitude." parmenides' point is that each form, which socrates believed to be complete (one), turns out to be an unbounded, incompletable series of subforms useles…Read more
  •  41
    Laurence Goldstein gives a straightforward and lively account of some of the central themes of Wittgenstein's writings on meaning, mind, and mathematics.
  •  41
  •  40
    The Micro-Computer as Logic Tutor
    Teaching Philosophy 7 (2): 109-114. 1984.
  •  40
    Categories of linguistic aspects and grelling's paradox
    Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (3). 1980.
  •  38
  •  34
  •  34
    Paradoxes: Their roots, range and resolution
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (4). 2004.
    Book Information Paradoxes: Their Roots, Range and Resolution. Paradoxes: Their Roots, Range and Resolution Nicholas Rescher , Chicago and La Salle : Open Court , 2001 , xxiii + 293 , US$24.95 ( paper ). By Nicholas Rescher. Open Court. Chicago and La Salle. Pp. xxiii + 293. US$24.95 (paper:).
  •  34
    To Let: Unsuccessful Stipulation, Bad Proof, and Paradox
    American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (1): 93. 2013.
    Letting is a common practice in mathematics. For example, we let x be the sum of the first n integers and, after a short proof, conclude that x = n(n+1)/2; we let J be the point where the bisectors of two of the angles of a triangle intersect and prove that this coincides with H, the point at which another pair of bisectors of the angles of that triangle intersect. Karl Weierstrass's colleagues, in an attempt to solve optimization problems, stipulated that the minimum area for a triangle with a …Read more
  •  34
    Strengthened paradoxes
    with Leonard Goddard
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58 (3). 1980.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  34
    Kripke, Pierre and Constantinescu
    The Reasoner 1 (5): 4-5. 2007.
    Refutes Cristian Constantinescu's proposed solution of Kripke's puzzle about belief.
  •  32
    (1983). Scientific scotism — The emperor's new trousers or has armstrong made some real strides? Australasian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 61, No. 1, pp. 40-57
  •  32
    Fallacious Reasoning
    Teaching Philosophy 18 (2): 139-146. 1995.
    The author recommends an involved study of logical fallacies in order to provide a database of testable hypotheses for error reasoning. The purpose of the study is to make the study of logical fallacies accessible to a wider audience. Following a recent study conducted by Ludwig Schlecht, the author presents a diagnostic method to illustrate how an argument can be fallacious from the breach of particular rational principles. The diagnosis method also serves as investigation into other forms of a…Read more
  •  30
    Only Joking?
    Philosophy Now 34 25-26. 2001.
    When is a joke morally dubious?
  •  29
    Universals and Scientific Realism
    Philosophical Quarterly 29 (117): 360-362. 1979.
  •  28
    Linguistic Representation
    Philosophical Quarterly 26 (103): 189-191. 1976.
  •  26
    A Buridanian discussion of desire, murder and democracy
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (4). 1992.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  25
    Unassertion
    Philosophia 18 (1): 119-121. 1988.