•  61
    This text argues that we must depart considerably from Frege's own views if we are to work towards an adequate conception of natural language.
  •  68
    Moral dilemmas
    Think 8 (22): 57-63. 2009.
    Could it be that one morally ought to do something morally bad? Some people think the answer is obviously ‘No’. Indeed, these theorists may say, it is contradictory to suppose that one morally ought to do something morally bad. Others hold that it is not a contradiction but a sad fact of life that one may be morally required to do something morally bad. This latter position is the one I'll be supporting. If it's the right view, it really matters in practical affairs. For example, almost everyone…Read more
  • Facts and Free Logic
    ProtoSociology 23. 2006.
  •  22
    Beyond Belief
    The Philosophers' Magazine 77 76-81. 2017.
  •  6
    Language and meaning
    In John Shand (ed.), Central Issues of Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  •  11
    Frege is now regarded as one of the world's greatest philosophers, and the founder of modern logic. Mark Sainsbury argues that we must depart considerably from Frege's views if we are to work towards an adequate conception of natural language. This is an outstanding contribution to philosophy of language and logic and will be invaluable to all those interested in Frege and the philosophy of language.
  •  24
    Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume 1: The Dawn of Analysis (review)
    Philosophical Studies 129 (3): 645-665. 2005.
    I discuss Soames's proposal that Moore could have avoided a central problem in his moral philosophy if he had utilized a method he himself pioneered in epistemology. The problem in Moore's moral philossophy concerns what it is for a moral claim to be self-evident. The method in Moore's epistemology concerns not denying the obvious. In view of the distance between something's being self-evident and its being obvious, it is suggested that Soames's proposal is mistaken
  •  13
    Fiction and Fictionalism (review)
    Disputatio 4 (29): 88-94. 2010.
  •  6
    Descartes
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (149): 453-458. 1987.
  •  129
    Russell on Acquaintance
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20 219-244. 1986.
    In Russell's Problems of Philosophy (PP), acquaintance is the basis of thought and also the basis of empirical knowledge. Thought is based on acquaintance, in that a thinker has to be acquainted with the basic constituents of his thoughts. Empirical knowledge is based on acquaintance, in that acquaintance is involved in perception, and perception is the ultimate source of all empirical knowledge.
  •  19
    Thinking About Things
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
    Mark Sainsbury presents an original account of how language works when describing mental states, based on a new theory of what is involved in attributing attitudes like thinking, hoping, and wanting. He offers solutions to longstanding puzzles about how we can direct our thought to such a diversity of things, including things that do not exist.
  • Indexicals and Reported Speech
    In J. W. Davis (ed.), Philosophical logic, D. Reidel. pp. 45-69. 1969.
  •  1
    Paradoxes
    Philosophy 65 (251): 106-111. 1990.
  •  1
    Referring descriptions
    In Marga Reimer & Anne Bezuidenhout (eds.), Descriptions and beyond, Oxford University Press. pp. 369--89. 2004.
  •  167
    Easy possibilities
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 907-919. 1997.
  •  43
    Paradoxes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 455-459. 1991.
  •  1
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 88 (1): 604-607. 1979.
  •  95
    Lessons for Vagueness from Scrambled Sorites
    Metaphysica 14 (2): 225-237. 2013.
    Vagueness demands many boundaries. Each is permissible, in that a thinker may without error use it to distinguish objects, though none is mandatory. This is revealed by a thought experiment—scrambled sorites—in which objects from a sorites series are presented in a random order, and subjects are required to make their judgments without access to any previous objects or their judgments concerning them.
  •  381
    Understanding as immersion
    Philosophical Issues 16 (1). 2006.
    Understanding has often been regarded as a kind of knowledge. This paper argues that this view is very implausible for understanding words. Instead, a proper account will be of the “analytic-genetic” variety: it will describe immersion in the practice of using a word in such a way that even those not previously equipped with the concepts the word expresses can become immersed. Meeting this condition requires attention to findings in developmental psychology. If you understand a declarative utter…Read more
  •  29
    Evidence for Meaning
    Mind and Language 1 (1): 64-82. 1986.
  •  196
    Spotty scope
    Analysis 66 (1): 17-22. 2006.
  •  43
    Logical Forms: An Introduction to Philosophical Logic
    with T. S. Champlin
    Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167): 243. 1992.
    Logical Forms explains both the detailed problems involved in finding logical forms and also the theoretical underpinnings of philosophical logic. In this revised edition, exercises are integrated throughout the book. The result is a genuinely interactive introduction which engages the reader in developing the argument. Each chapter concludes with updated notes to guide further reading
  •  55
    I_– _R.M. Sainsbury
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1): 243-269. 1999.
  •  78
    Russell on constructions and fictions
    Theoria 46 (1): 19-36. 1980.
    Russell says that logical constructions are fictions. Does this show that he took them not to be real things?
  •  33
    Facts and Free Logic
    ProtoSociology 26. 2006.
    Comment on S. Neale's, "Facts and Free Logic".
  •  5
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (2): 211-215. 1985.
  •  42
    Rational dialetheism is the view that for some contradictions, it is rational to believe that they are true. The view, associated with the work of among others, Graham Priest, looks as if it must lead to absurd consequences, and the present paper is an unsuccessful attempt to find them. In particular, I suggest that there is no non-question-begging account of acceptance, denial and negation which can be brought to bear against the rational dialetheist. Finally, I consider the prospect of attacki…Read more
  •  134
    What logic should we think with?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51 1-17. 2002.
    Logic ought to guide our thinking. It is better, more rational, more intelligent to think logically than to think illogically. Illogical thought leads to bad judgment and error. In any case, if logic had no role to play as a guide to thought, why should we bother with it?The somewhat naïve opinions of the previous paragraph are subject to attack from many sides. It may be objected that an activity does not count as thinking at all unless it is at least minimally logical, so logic is constitutive…Read more