•  768
    Two ways to smoke a cigarette
    Ratio 14 (4). 2001.
    In the early part of the paper, I attempt to explain a dispute between two parties who endorse the compositionality of language but disagree about its implications: Paul Horwich, and Jerry Fodor and Ernest Lepore. In the remainder of the paper, I challenge the thesis on which they are agreed, that compositionality can be taken for granted. I suggest that it is not clear what compositionality involves nor whether it obtains. I consider some kinds of apparent counterexamples, and compositionalist …Read more
  •  70
    Degrees of Belief and Degrees of Truth
    Philosophical Papers 15 (2-3): 97-106. 1986.
    No abstract
  • Language and meaning
    In John Shand (ed.), Central Issues in Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  •  51
    Semantics by Proxy
    Analysis 37 (2). 1977.
    Many theories provide semantics for English by proxy of semantics for the "logical form" of English sentences. The paper presents a dilemma: if there is no algorithm for moving between English and logical form, English itself has not been given a semantic theory. But if there is an algorithm, it can be incorporated in the theory, which would then apply directly to English. In the worst case, logical form is an obstacle to providing semantics for English. In the best case, it is unnecessary.
  •  578
    Representing unicorns: how to think about intensionality
    In G. Currie, P. Kotatko & M. Pokorny (eds.), Mimesis: Metaphysics, Cognition, Pragmatics, College Publications. 2012.
    The paper focuses on two apparent paradoxes arising from our use of intensional verbs: first, their object can be something which does not exist, i.e. something which is nothing; second, the fact that entailment from a qualified to a non-qualified object is not guaranteed. In this paper, I suggest that the problems share a solution, insofar as they arise in connection with intensional verbs that ascribe mental states. The solution turns on (I) a properly intensional or nonrelational notion of re…Read more
  •  73
    IX*—Understanding and Theories of Meaning
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80 (1): 127-144. 1980.
    R. M. Sainsbury; IX*—Understanding and Theories of Meaning, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 80, Issue 1, 1 June 1980, Pages 127–144, https://doi.
  •  52
    Russell on Acquaintance
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20 219-244. 1986.
    In Russell's Problems of Philosophy (PP), acquaintance is the basis of thought and also the basis of empirical knowledge. Thought is based on acquaintance, in that a thinker has to be acquainted with the basic constituents of his thoughts. Empirical knowledge is based on acquaintance, in that acquaintance is involved in perception, and perception is the ultimate source of all empirical knowledge.
  •  76
    Fiction and Acceptance-Relative Truth, Belief and Assertion
    In Franck Lihoreau (ed.), Truth in Fiction, Ontos Verlag. pp. 38--137. 2010.
  •  4
    Philosophical logic
    In A. C. Grayling (ed.), Philosophy: A Guide Through the Subject, Oxford University Press. 1995.
  •  108
  •  31
    Austerity and Openness
    In Cynthia Macdonald & Graham Macdonald (eds.), McDowell and his critics, Blackwell. pp. 6--1. 2006.
    Article
  •  35
    Evans envisaged a language containing both Russellian and descriptive names. A language with descriptive names, which can contribute to truth conditions even if they have no bearer, needs a free logical truth theory. But a metalanguage with this logic threatens to emasculate Russellian names. The paper details this problem and shows, on Evans's behalf, how it might be resolved.
  •  83
    Sorites paradoxes and the transition question
    Philosophical Papers 21 (3): 177-190. 1992.
    This discusses the kind of paradox that has since become known as "the forced march sorites", here called "the transition question". The question is whether this is really a new kind of paradox, or the familiar sorites in unfamiliar garb. The author argues that resources adequate to deal with ordinary sorites are sufficient to deal with the transition question, and tentatively proposes an affirmative answer.
  •  16
    III*—Tolerating Vagueness
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 89 (1): 33-48. 1989.
    R. M. Sainsbury; III*—Tolerating Vagueness, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 89, Issue 1, 1 June 1989, Pages 33–48, https://doi.org/10.1093/arist.
  •  503
    one hand, it raises fundamental doubts about the Davidsonian project, which seems to involve isolating specifically semantic knowledge from any other knowledge or skill in a way reflected by the ideal of homophony. Indexicality forces a departure from this ideal, and so from the aspiration of deriving the truth conditions of an arbitrary utterance on the basis simply of axioms which could hope to represent purely semantic knowledge. In defence of Davidson, I argue that once his original idea for…Read more
  •  34
    Hume seems to tell us that our ideas are copies of our corresponding impres-sions, that we have an idea of necessary connection, but that we have no corresponding impression, since nothing can be known to be really necessarily connected. The paper considers two ways of reinterpreting the doctrine of the origins of ideas so as to avoid the apparent inconsistency. If we see the doctrine as concerned primarily with establishing conditions under which we possess an idea, there is no need for an idea…Read more
  •  1
    Referring descriptions
    In Marga Reimer & Anne Bezuidenhout (eds.), Descriptions and Beyond, Oxford University Press. pp. 369--89. 2004.
  •  167
    Easy possibilities
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 907-919. 1997.
  •  42
    Paradoxes
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 455-459. 1991.
  •  1
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 88 (1): 604-607. 1979.
  •  381
    Understanding as immersion
    Philosophical Issues 16 (1). 2006.
    Understanding has often been regarded as a kind of knowledge. This paper argues that this view is very implausible for understanding words. Instead, a proper account will be of the “analytic-genetic” variety: it will describe immersion in the practice of using a word in such a way that even those not previously equipped with the concepts the word expresses can become immersed. Meeting this condition requires attention to findings in developmental psychology. If you understand a declarative utter…Read more
  •  29
    Evidence for Meaning
    Mind and Language 1 (1): 64-82. 1986.
  •  95
    Lessons for Vagueness from Scrambled Sorites
    Metaphysica 14 (2): 225-237. 2013.
    Vagueness demands many boundaries. Each is permissible, in that a thinker may without error use it to distinguish objects, though none is mandatory. This is revealed by a thought experiment—scrambled sorites—in which objects from a sorites series are presented in a random order, and subjects are required to make their judgments without access to any previous objects or their judgments concerning them.
  •  187
    Spotty scope
    Analysis 66 (1): 17-22. 2006.
  •  41
    Logical Forms: An Introduction to Philosophical Logic
    with T. S. Champlin
    Philosophical Quarterly 42 (167): 243. 1992.
    Logical Forms explains both the detailed problems involved in finding logical forms and also the theoretical underpinnings of philosophical logic. In this revised edition, exercises are integrated throughout the book. The result is a genuinely interactive introduction which engages the reader in developing the argument. Each chapter concludes with updated notes to guide further reading
  •  50
    I_– _R.M. Sainsbury
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1): 243-269. 1999.
  •  78
    Russell on constructions and fictions
    Theoria 46 (1): 19-36. 1980.
    Russell says that logical constructions are fictions. Does this show that he took them not to be real things?