•  372
    Animals, thoughts and concepts
    Synthese 123 (1): 35-104. 2000.
      There are three main positions on animalthought: lingualism denies that non-linguistic animalshave any thoughts; mentalism maintains that theirthoughts differ from ours only in degree, due totheir different perceptual inputs; an intermediateposition, occupied by common sense and Wittgenstein,maintains that animals can have thoughts of a simplekind. This paper argues in favor of an intermediateposition. It considers the most important arguments infavor of lingualism, namely those inspired byDav…Read more
  •  154
    From armchair to reality?
    Ratio 23 (3): 339-348. 2010.
  •  176
    The linguistic doctrine revisited
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 (1): 143-170. 2003.
    At present, there is an almost universal consensus that the linguistic doctrine of logical necessity is grotesque. This paper explores avenues for rehabilitating a limited version of the doctrine, according to which the special status of analytic statements like 'All vixens are female' is to be explained by reference to language. Far from being grotesque, this appeal to language has a respectable philosophical pedigree and chimes with common sense, as Quine came to realize. The problem lies in d…Read more
  •  305
    Concepts, conceptual schemes and grammar
    Philosophia 37 (4): 653-668. 2009.
    This paper considers the connection between concepts, conceptual schemes and grammar in Wittgenstein’s last writings. It lists eight claims about concepts that one can garner from these writings. It then focuses on one of them, namely that there is an important difference between conceptual and factual problems and investigations. That claim draws in its wake other claims, all of them revolving around the idea of a conceptual scheme, what Wittgenstein calls a ‘grammar’. I explain why Wittgenstei…Read more
  •  61
    Subjective, intersubjective, objective
    Philosophical Investigations 26 (4). 2003.
    Books reviewed: Donald Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective.
  •  87
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 0, Issue 0, Page 1-5, Ahead of Print.
  •  20
    Wittgenstein's `Philosophical Investigations': Text and Context
    with Robert L. Arrington
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (176): 392-394. 1994.
  •  44
    Wie wichtig ist Erkenntnistheorie?
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 56 (1). 2002.
    In der zeitgenössischen analytischen Philosophe wird oft behauptet, die Erkenntnistheorie sei weniger fundamental als die Ontologie, da sich aus Aussagen über unser Erkenntnisvermögen keine Aussagen über die Wirklichkeit ableiten lassen und die Frage nach der Beschaffenheit der Wirklichkeit der Frage nach ihrer Erkennbarkeit vorausgeht. Dagegen verteidige ich folgende Thesen: eine Form der Erkenntnistheorie—die Auseinandersetzung mit der Skepsis —ist nicht fundamental; eine andere Form—die Ausei…Read more
  •  2
    Meaning, rules, and conventions
    In David K. Levy & Edoardo Zamuner (eds.), Wittgenstein’s Enduring Arguments, Routledge. 2008.
  •  260
    Wittgenstein and Analytic Philosophy: Essays for P. M. S. Hacker (edited book)
    with John Hyman
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Thirteen leading contributors offer new essays in honour of the eminent philosopher and Wittgenstein scholar Peter Hacker. They discuss issues in the interpretation of Wittgenstein, investigate central topics in the history of analytic philosophy, and explore and assess Wittgensteinian ideas about language, mind, action, ethics, and religion.
  •  3
    Does language require conventions
    In Pasquale Frascolla, Diego Marconi & Alberto Voltolini (eds.), Wittgenstein: Mind, Meaning and Metaphilosophy, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 85--112. 2010.
  •  115
    Concepts, abilities, and propositions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 81 (1): 115-134. 2010.
    This article investigates whether the concept of a concept can be given a fairly uniform explanation through a 'cognitivist' account, one that accepts that concepts exist independently of individual subjects, yet nonetheless invokes mental achievements and capacities. I consider various variants of such an account, which identify a concept, respectively, with a certain kind of abilitiy, rule and way of thinking. All of them are confronted with what I call the 'proposition problem', namely that u…Read more
  •  46
    Truth without People?
    Philosophy 72 (279). 1997.
    There is a venerable tradition according to which the concept of truth is totally independent of human beings, their actions and beliefs, because truth consists in the correspondence of mind-independentpropositions to a mind-independent reality. For want of arespect. One way of doing so is relativism, the idea that whether a belief is true or false depends on the point of view of individuals or communities. A closely related position is a consensus theory of truth, according to which a belief is…Read more
  •  170
    Analytic philosophy and history: A mismatch?
    Mind 117 (468): 867-897. 2008.
    In recent years, even some of its own practitioners have accused analytic philosophy of lacking historical awareness. My aim is to show that analytic philosophy and history are not such a mismatch after all. Against the objection that analytic philosophers have unduly ignored the past I argue that for the most part they only resist strong versions of historicism, and for good reasons. The history of philosophy is not the whole of philosophy, as extreme historicists maintain, nor is it indispensa…Read more
  •  198
    This paper discusses conceptual relativism. The main focus is on the contrasting ideas of Wittgenstein and Davidson, with Quine, Kuhn, Feyerabend and Hacker in supporting roles. I distinguish conceptual from alethic and ontological relativism, defend a distinction between conceptual scheme and empirical content, and reject the Davidsonian argument against the possibility of alternative conceptual schemes: there can be conceptual diversity without failure of translation, and failure of translatio…Read more
  •  155
    Nonsense Made Intelligible
    Erkenntnis 80 (1): 111-136. 2015.
    My topic is the relation between nonsense and intelligibility, and the contrast between nonsense and falsehood which played a pivotal role in the rise of analytic philosophy . I shall pursue three lines of inquiry. First I shall briefly consider the positive case, namely linguistic understanding . Secondly, I shall consider the negative case—different breakdowns of understanding and connected forms of failure to make sense . Third, I shall criticize three important misconceptions of nonsense and…Read more
  •  143
    What is Analytic Philosophy?
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    Analytic philosophy is roughly a hundred years old, and it is now the dominant force within Western philosophy. Interest in its historical development is increasing, but there has hitherto been no sustained attempt to elucidate what it currently amounts to, and how it differs from so-called 'continental' philosophy. In this rich and wide-ranging book, Hans Johann Glock argues that analytic philosophy is a loose movement held together both by ties of influence and by various 'family resemblances'…Read more
  • Grammar and Methodology: On Wittgenstein's Later Conception of Philosophy
    Dissertation, University of Oxford (United Kingdom). 1989.
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. Requires signed TDF. ;Even among Wittgenstein's admirers, his conception of philosophy as a therapy for conceptual confusion is generally considered to be the weakest part of his later work. It seems to consist of slogans, which are unsupported by argument and belied by his own 'theory construction'. It may even be self-refuting--a philosophical theory that denies the possibility of philosophical theory. ;Unless these objections can be …Read more
  •  22
    Critical discussion
    Erkenntnis 36 (1): 117-128. 1992.
    v. Savigny's commentary is a remarkable achievement and essential reading for all scholars of the Investigations. It brings to the exegetical enterprise something new and important — the challenge of an immanent approach and the tool of German philology. However, some of the potential gains may be lost by his leitmotiv of a tight master-scheme. In my view this ‘central theses’ scheme presses Wittgenstein's multifaceted masterpiece into an unsuitable Procrustean bed and tends to impoverish v. Sav…Read more
  •  141
    This paper considers the question of whether there is a human-animal or ‘anthropological difference'. It starts with a historical introduction to the project of philosophical anthropology. Section 2 explains the philosophical quest for an anthropological difference. Sections 3-4 are methodological and explain how philosophical anthropology should be pursued in my view, namely as impure conceptual analysis. The following two sections discuss two fundamental objections to the very idea of such a d…Read more
  •  40
    A Wittgenstein Dictionary
    Wiley-Blackwell. 1996.
    This lucid and accessible dictionary presents technical terms that Wittgenstein introduced into philosophical debate or transformed substantially, and also topics to which he made a substantial contribution. Hans-Johann Glock places Wittgenstein's ideas in their relevance to current debates. The entries delineate Wittgenstein's lines of argument on particular issues, assessing their strengths and weaknesses, and shed light on fundamental exegetical controversies. The dictionary entries are prefa…Read more
  •  15
    Rise of Analytic Philosophy (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 1997.
    They try to identify key themes and methods in 20th century analytical philosophy and assess various conceptions of what analytical philosophy like that of Dummett is by comparing them with the methodology and practice of eminent analytical philosophers.
  •  50
    Zurich
    The Philosophers' Magazine 56 (56): 47-50. 2012.
  •  50
    Précis of What is Analytic Philosophy?
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 30 (1). 2011.