-
"Postema's Account of Integrity"In Thomas da Rosa de Bustamante & Thiago Lopes Decat (eds.), Philosophy of law as an integral part of philosophy: essays on the jurisprudence of Gerald J. Postema, Hart Publishing, an Imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing. pp. 47-79. 2020.In his “Integrity: Justice in Work Clothes,” Postema assumes the task of showing that integrity is a genuine moral value of political communities, distinct from other values such as justice and fairness. Postema’s conception of integrity borrows much from Dworkin’s, but also differs from it in an important respect. As anyone familiar with Dworkin’s theory would expect, Postema’s idea of integrity is a kind of fidelity in laws (“practical directives”) and policies to principles arising from wh…Read more
-
“How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”In “How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”, Oxford University Press. pp. 75-102. 2013.The social fact thesis, is, roughly, that law is ultimately a matter of social fact. Mark Greenberg and Kevin Toh have launched transcendental arguments against important or interesting general versions of the social fact thesis. Together, they can be read as posing a dilemma for the thesis. Suppose that many correct assertions of law are normative. Then, according to Toh, the considerations in virtue of which they are correct cannot ultimately be social facts, because the derivation of any …Read more
-
6The retroactivity problemIn Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & Harry S. Silverstein (eds.), Time and Identity, Bradford. 2010.This chapter discusses the retroactivity problem and how it arises when the idea that events occurring after a person’s life can harm that person is pursued. The common objection to this dilemma is the “no subject” type of response. The retroactivity problem is the result of making several assumptions jointly, many of which are initially plausible but none of which are actually defended. The first of these assumptions is referred to as Worse-Off, which states that an event harms a person only if…Read more
-
Mark Greenberg on Legal PositivismIn Torben Spaak (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism, Cambridge University Press. 2021.Mark Greenberg has made a transcendental attack on a metaphysical position that some notable legal positivists have held -- namely, that law is ultimately grounded in social facts. He has also pressed legal positivism at a point of perceived vulnerability – the failure of such positivists to develop and defend a compelling theory of legal content. Moreover, in his Moral Impact Theory of law, he preserves a necessary connection between legal obligations and good reasons for action that is absen…Read more
-
Disposition of RemainsIn Christopher Berry Gray (ed.), The philosophy of law: an encyclopedia, Garland. 1999.
-
Postema's account of integrityIn Thomas da Rosa de Bustamante & Thiago Lopes Decat (eds.), Philosophy of law as an integral part of philosophy: essays on the jurisprudence of Gerald J. Postema, Hart Publishing, an Imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing. 2020.
-
The relevance of literary interpretationIn Thomas da Rosa de Bustamante & Margaret Martin (eds.), New essays on the Fish-Dworkin debate, Hart Publishing, an Imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing. 2023.
-
40The parti-resultantness of requirement: An explanation that failedPhilosophical Studies 37 (3). 1980.
-
24Review of Ferdinand David Schoeman: Privacy and Social Freedom (review)Ethics 105 (2): 421-422. 1995.
-
Does dignity help in thinking about paternalism?In Salman Khurshid, Lokendra Malik & Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco (eds.), Dignity in the legal and political philosophy of Ronald Dworkin, Oxford University Press. 2018.
-
Examining Legal Restrictions on the RetardedIn L. M. Kopelman & J. C. Moskop (eds.), Ethics and Mental Retardation, Springer Verlag. pp. 209-221. 1984.
-
On Universal Relevance in Legal ReasoningLaw and Philosophy 3 1-23. 1984.The purpose of this essay is to defend a claim that a certain consideration, which I call unworkability, is universally and necessarily relevant to legal reasoning. By that I mean that it is a consideration that must carry legal weight in the justification of some judicial decisions in every legal system in which (1) all disputed matters of law can be adjudicated, and (2) all judicial decisions are to be legally justified. Unworkability's necessary relevance has important implications for a theo…Read more
-
Responsibility and the Normative Order AssumptionLaw and Contemporary Problems 49 (summer): 81-88. 1986.
-
1Disposition of RemainsIn Christopher Berry Gray (ed.), The philosophy of law: an encyclopedia, Garland. 1999.This is a reference work surveying the literature (as of the publication date) on treatment of the remains of human beings. I discuss leading views on the possibility of posthumous harm, posthumous rights, and rights of the living in the bodies of the dead.
-
Mark Greenberg on Legal PositivismIn Torben Spaak (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Legal Positivism, Cambridge University Press. 2021.In various works, Mark Greenberg has positioned himself as an important critic of legal positivism. He has made a transcendental attack on a metaphysical position that some notable legal positivists have held -- namely, that law is ultimately grounded in social facts. He has pressed legal positivism at a point of perceived vulnerability – the failure of such positivists to develop and defend a compelling theory of legal content. Moreover, in his Moral Impact Theory of law, he preserves a nece…Read more
-
1The Law of the StreetIn James Penner & Mark McBride (eds.), New Essays on the Nature of Legal Reasoning, Hart Publishing. 2022.Everyone agrees that law is a constituent of social reality. Law seems to be a system by which conduct is governed and guided. Its usefulness consists, in part, on its ability to govern and guide conduct in its characteristic way. If laws guides the conduct of lay law subjects, then it must be (really) possible for the content of the laws governing their conduct to be known by them under standard social conditions. Moreover, if some degree of efficacy in guiding and governing the conduct of …Read more
-
39A puzzle about legal systems and democratic theoryJurisprudence 11 (2): 157-168. 2020.Older statutes sometimes alter the legal content of newer statutes in a way not apparent from the text of the newer statutes. The puzzle is how, even if a new statute is the choice of the current polis, the legal content created in part by the elderly statute is also the choice of the current polis. I consider several possible answers, including a legislative intent account and Dworkin’s, and argue that none of them is satisfactory. I then offer my own account, the De Re Account, which depends…Read more
-
11Book Review of Ferdinand Schoeman, Privacy and Social Freedom (review)Ethics 105 (2): 421-422. 1995.
-
Review: Philip Schuchman, Problems of Knowledge in Legal Scholarship Reviewed byPhilosophy in Review 1 (5): 221-224. 1981.
-
“How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”In “How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”, Oxford University Press. pp. 75-102. 2013.The social fact thesis, is, roughly, that law is ultimately a matter of social fact. Mark Greenberg and Kevin Toh have launched transcendental arguments against important or interesting general versions of the social fact thesis. Together, they can be read as posing a dilemma for the thesis. Suppose that many correct assertions of law are normative. Then, according to Toh, the considerations in virtue of which they are correct cannot ultimately be social facts, because the derivation of any …Read more
-
135The role of coherence in legal reasoningLaw and Philosophy 3 (3). 1984.Many contemporary philosophers of law agree that a necessary condition for a decision to be legally justified, even in a hard case, is that it coheres with established law. Some, namely Sartorius and Dworkin, have gone beyond that relatively uncontroversial claim and described the role of coherence in legal justification as analogous to its role in moral and scientific justification, on contemporary theories. In this, I argue, they are mistaken. Specifically, coherence in legal justification is …Read more
-
51That Makes It WorseThe Monist 63 (2): 228-245. 1980.This is an essay on aggravating circumstances. Rather than defend a thesis that particular things ought to be considered aggravating circumstances to wrongdoing, I assume general agreement about major sorts of aggravating circumstances; and I ask instead how they work and what their operation reveals about moral standards in general and minimal expectations in particular. In the final section of this essay, I briefly consider what can be said in defense of the commonsense principle that punish…Read more
-
60How a statute appliesLegal Theory 12 (1): 71-112. 2006.This essay presents a new theory of statutory application that is superior to two competitors. One of the competitors claims that statutory directives apply to act-tokens fitting the legislature's intention. The other holds that statutes apply to act-tokens that are of the genuine kinds named by the classifying words. These theories solve certain problems badly or not at all, respectively: (1) accounting for the capacity of statutes for epistemic guidance; and (2) avoiding literalism. Both do a …Read more
-
49D-theories, Discretion, and the Justification of AdjudicationSocial Theory and Practice 5 (3-4): 331-345. 1980.This essay challenges Dworkin's account of the virtues and consistency of applying the right answer as given by a certain interpretive theory of local law (hereafter, the D-theory) with democratic theory. D-theory adjudication does not have all the virtues Dworkin claims for it. It may involve judicial law-creation as well, rather than being confined to the discovery of preexisting legal rights. It may also involve any of the morally objectionable features of judicial law-creation, including …Read more
-
66Harming the dead, once againEthics 96 (1): 162-164. 1985.This article responds to criticism by Don Marquis of my previous article, "Harming Someone after His Death." I argue that because the idea of surviving interests in not plausible, the harm-as-loss-theory is not on all fours with the harm-as-invasion-of-interests theory (especially when it comes to the harm of murder), and that the former is preferable.
Raleigh, North Carolina, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Value Theory |
Areas of Interest
Value Theory |