•  4
    Prior's Theory of Propositions
    Analysis 37 (3): 104-112. 1977.
  •  79
    Mathematical Relativism
    with Hugly Philip and Sayward Charles
    History and Philosophy of Logic 10 (1): 53-65. 1989.
    We set out a doctrine about truth for the statements of mathematics?a doctrine which we think is a worthy competitor to realist views in the philosophy of mathematics?and argue that this doctrine, which we shall call ?mathematical relativism?, withstands objections better than do other non-realist accounts
  •  354
    Applying the concept of pain
    Iyyun 52 (July): 290-300. 2003.
    This paper reaches the conclusion that, while there are ordinary cases in which the pretending possibility is reasonable, these cases always contain some element that makes it reasonable. This will be the element we ask for when we ask why pretending possibility is raised. Knowledge that someone else is in pain is a matter of eliminating the proposed element or neutralizing its pain-negating aspect.
  • Chapter 8: Thesis One
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 215-240. 2006.
  •  38
    Roman Suzuko on Situational Identity
    Sorites 15 42-49. 2004.
    This paper gives a semantical account for the (i)ordinary propositional calculus, enriched with quantifiers binding variables standing for sentences, and with an identity-function with sentences as arguments; (ii)the ordinary theory of quantification applied to the special quantifiers; and (iii)ordinary laws of identity applied to the special function. The account includes some thoughts of Roman Suszko as well as some thoughts of Wittgenstein's Tractatus.
  •  65
    Two concepts of truth
    Philosophical Studies 70 (1). 1993.
    In this paper the authors recapitulate, justify, and defend against criticism the extension of the redundancy theory of truth to cover a wide range of uses of ‘true’ and ‘false’. In this they are guided by the work of A. N. Prior. They argue Prior was right about the scope and limits of the redundancy theory and that the line he drew between those uses of ‘true’ which are and are not susceptible to treatment via redundancy serves to distinguish two important and mutually irreducible types of tru…Read more
  •  16
    Austin and perception
    Acta Analytica 16 (27): 169-193. 2001.
    Some of Austin's general statements about the doctrines of sense-datum philosophy are reviewed. It is concluded that Austin thought that in these doctrines "directly see" is given a new but inadequately explained and defined use. Were this so, the philosophical use of "directly see" would lack a definite sense and this would correspondingly affect the doctrines. They would lack definite truth-value. Against this, it is argued that the philosopher's use of "directly see" does not support Austin's…Read more
  • Chapter 6: Arithmetic and Necessity
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 159-182. 2006.
  •  55
    Nagel, Internalism, and Relativism
    Journal of Philosophical Research 1990 310-319. 1990.
    In this paper we give (1) a new interpretation to Nagel’s THE POSSIBILITY OF ALTRUISM and (2) use that interpretation to show that internalism and anti-realism are compatible, despite appearances to the contrary.
  •  102
    Quine’s Way Out
    Analysis 36 (1): 28-37. 1975.
    As a way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes Quine has suggested: that semantical expressions such as ‘true’ and ‘true of’ be used with numerical subscripts; that when a truth locution T is applied to a sentence S, the subscript on T is greater than any within S; otherwise, the result of applying T to S is ill formed. A problem is that this introduces infinitely many semantical primitives. The paper suggests a way around the problem. The paper raises a further problem, leaving it open whet…Read more
  •  121
    Is heaven a possible world?
    with Douglas Erlandson
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 12 (1). 1981.
    The goal of theodicy is to show how God could create our world with all its evil. This paper argues that the theodicist can achieve her goal only if she gives up one of these three propositions: (1) evil does not exist in heaven; (2) heaven is better than the present world; (3) heaven is a possible world. Second, it is argued that the theodicist can reject (3) without giving up her belief that heaven exists, so that (3) is her best alternative.
  •  31
    More on assertion and belief
    Philosophical Studies 22 (1-2). 1971.
    In an earlier paper Sayward argued that a speaker could not make an assertion by uttering a sentence of form “p, but I believe not-p” given that the speaker spoke honestly and literally. Robert Imlay criticized some things said in that earlier paper. This paper responds to those criticisms.
  •  39
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophishe Studien 41 150-173. 1991.
    A case against Prior’s theory of propositions goes thus: (1) everyday propositional generalizations are not substitutional; (2) Priorean quantifications are not objectual; (3) quantifications are substitutional if not objectual; (4) thus, Priorean quantifications are substitutional; (5) thus that Priorean quantifications are not ontologically committed to propositions provides no basis for a similar claim about our everyday propositional generalizations. Prior agrees with (1) and (2). He rejects…Read more
  •  96
    What is a second order theory committed to?
    Erkenntnis 20 (1). 1983.
    The paper argues that no second order theory is ontologically commited to anything beyond what its individual variables range over.
  •  28
    Do we need models?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (3): 414-422. 1987.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a nondenotational semantics for first-order languages which will match one for one each distribution of truth-values available in terms of a denotational semantics.
  •  262
    Quine’s way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes (Ways of Paradox, pp. 9-10) is criticized. The criticism is based on three premises: (1) no learnable language has infinitely many semantical primitives; (2) any language of which Quine’s theory is true has infinitely many semantical primitives; (3) English is a learnable language. The conclusion drawn is that Quine’s theory is not true of English.
  •  123
    Determining whether the law of excluded middle requires bivalence depends upon whether we are talking about sentences or propositions. If we are talking about sentences, neither side has a decisive case. If we are talking of propositions, there is a strong argument on the side of those who say the excluded middle does require bivalence. I argue that all challenges to this argument can be met.
  •  51
    Is English inconsistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3). 1980.
    The significance of the semantical paradoxes for natural languages is examined. If Tarski’s reflections on the issue are correct, English is inconsistent. Paul Ziff responds to Tarskian reflections by arguing to the conclusion that no natural language is or can be inconsistent. The authors reject Ziff’s argument, but they defend something similar to its conclusion: no language, natural or otherwise, is or can be inconsistent in the way that Tarski holds languages capable of formulating the Epime…Read more
  •  89
    The Province of Logic
    Analysis 36 (1): 47-48. 1975.
    Quine criticizes Strawson’s account of the province of logic. Robert Hadley proposes a refutation of Quine. This paper proposes a refutation of Hadley.
  •  376
    What’s So Special About Sentences?
    Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 28 (4): 409-25. 1995.
    This paper is a discussion of Frege's maxim that it is only in the context of a sentence that a word has a meaning. Quine reads the maxim as saying that the sentence is the fundamental unit of significance. Dummett rejects this as a truism. But it is not a truism since it stands in opposition to a conception of meaning held by John Locke and others. The maxim denies that a word has a sense independently of any sentence in which it occurs. Dummett says this denial is inconsistent with the fact th…Read more
  •  18
    Should persons be sacrificed for the general welfare?
    Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (2): 149-152. 1982.
    It is argued that Robert Nozick is wrong in asserting that persons should not be sacrificed for the general welfare.
  •  13
    The Internal/External Question
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 47 (1): 31-41. 1994.
  •  85
    A defense of mill on other minds
    Dialectica 57 (3). 2003.
    This paper seeks to explain why the argument from analogy seems strong to an analogist such as Mill and weak to the skeptic. The inference from observed behavior to the existence of feelings, sensations, etc., in other subjects is justified, but its justification depends on taking observed behavior and feelings, sensations, and so on, to be not merely correlated, but connected. It is claimed that this is what Mill had in mind.
  • Chapter 2: Notes to Grundlagen
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 45-72. 2006.
  •  768
    Quine and his Critics on Truth-Functionality and Extensionality
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 16 (1): 45-63. 2007.
    Quine argues that if sentences that are set theoretically equivalent are interchangeable salva veritate, then all transparent operators are truth-functional. Criticisms of this argument fail to take into account the conditional character of the conclusion. Quine also argues that, for any person P with minimal logical acuity, if ‘belief’ has a sense in which it is a transparent operator, then, in that sense of the word, P believes everything if P believes anything. The suggestion is made that he …Read more
  •  3
    Replies to Commentaries
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 (1): 369-386. 2006.
  •  166
    A problem about conversational implicature
    Linguistics and Philosophy 3 (1). 1979.
    Conversational implicatures are easy to grasp for the most part. But it is another matter to give a rational reconstruction of how they are grasped. We argue that Grice's attempt to do this fails. We distinguish two sorts of cases: (1) those in which we grasp the implicature by asking ourselves what would the speaker have to believe given that what he said is such as is required by the talk exchange; (2) those in which we grasp the implicature by asking ourselves why it is that what the speaker …Read more
  •  299
    Must Synonymous Predicates be Coextensive?
    Logique Et Analyse 95 (95): 430-435. 1981.
    Two cases are distinguished. In one case two predicates belong to distinct languages. A straight-forward argument is presented that the predicates might be synonymous without being coextensive. In the second case the predicates belong to the same language. Here the issue is more involved, but the same conclusion is reached.