• Subjective Time: From Past to Future
    In , Mit Press. pp. 309-321. 2014.
  • The Disunity of Time
    In , Mit Press. pp. 657-663. 2014.
  •  17
    Microcognition
    with Andy Clark
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 706. 1992.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 96 (384): 583-588. 1987.
  •  8
    Not Dead Yet: Fragility and Phenomenology in a Time of Plague
    Constructivist Foundations 16 (3): 253-255. 2021.
    One manifestation of fragility in the pandemic era is the fragility of social systems, and especially the revealed instability of science and other forms of understanding, when opposed to the …
  •  18
  •  40
    Protention and Predictive Processing: The Wave of the Future
    Constructivist Foundations 13 (1): 98-99. 2017.
    Gallagher’s main claim can be enhanced neurophenomenologically. In his 1907 lectures Thing and Space, Husserl argued that perception in general is enactive. Moreover, the neuroscientific theory of predictive processing connects neatly to a future-oriented phenomenology.
  • The Limits of Cognitive Liberalism
    Behavior and Philosophy 14 (1): 1. 1986.
  •  2
    A novel theory
    The Philosophers' Magazine 26 49-50. 2004.
  •  11
    Time after time
    In Shimon Edelman, Tomer Fekete & Neta Zach (eds.), Being in Time: Dynamical Models of Phenomenal Experience, John Benjamins. pp. 88--1. 2012.
  •  53
    A novel theory
    The Philosophers' Magazine 26 (26): 49-50. 2004.
  •  24
    The limits of cognitive liberalism
    Behaviorism 14 (1): 1-14. 1986.
    The central characteristic of cognitive explanations of behavior is the appeal to inner representations. I examine the grounds which justify representational explanations, seeking the minimum conditions which organisms must meet to be candidates for such explanations. I first discuss Fodor's proposal that representationality be attributed to systems which respond to nonnomic properties, arguing that the distinction between the nomic and nonnomic in perception is fatally ambiguous. Then I turn to…Read more
  •  51
    An innovative theory of consciousness, drawing on the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl and supported by brain-imaging, presented in the form of a hardboiled ..
  •  42
    Consciousness should not mean, but be
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1): 158-159. 1999.
    O'Brien & Opie's vehicle hypothesis is an attractive framework for the study of consciousness. To fully embrace the hypothesis, however, two of the authors' claims should be extended: first, since phenomenal content is entirely dependent on occurrent brain events and only contingently correlated with external events, it is no longer necessary to regard states of consciousness as representations. Second, the authors' insistence that only stable states of a neural network are conscious seems ad ho…Read more
  •  62
    Connectionist hysteria: Reducing a Freudian case study to a network model
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 1 (2): 69-88. 1994.
    Connectionism—also known as parallel distributed processing, or neural network modeling—offers promise as a framework to unite clinical and cognitive psychology, and as a tool for studying conscious and unconscious mental activity. This paper describes a neural network model of the case study of Lucy R., from Freud and Breuer's Studies on Hysteria. Though very simple in architecture, the network spontaneously displays analogues of repression and hallucination, corresponding to Lucy R.'s symptoms…Read more
  •  62
    A philosophical zombie is a being indistinguishable from an ordinary human in every observable respect, but lacking subjective consciousness. Zombiehood implies *linguistic indiscriminability*, the zombie tendency to talk and even do philosophy of mind in language indiscriminable from ordinary discourse. Zombies thus speak *Zombish*, indistinguishable from English but radically distinct in reference for mental terms. The fate of zombies ultimately depends on whether Zombish can be consistently i…Read more
  •  5
    adiant Cool" has the makings of a gripping noir thriller: a missing body, a tough-talking female sleuth and a mustachioed Russian agent mixed up in a shadowy plot to take over the world. But the novel, by Dan Lloyd, a neurophilosopher at Trinity College in Hartford, is also a serious work of scholarship, the unlikely vehicle for an abstruse new theory of consciousness.
  • Simple Minds
    Behavior and Philosophy 19 (2): 91-102. 1991.
  •  40
    Neural correlates of temporality: Default mode variability and temporal awareness
    Consciousness and Cognition 21 (2): 695-703. 2012.
    The continual background awareness of duration is an essential structure of consciousness, conferring temporal extension to the many objects of awareness within the evanescent sensory present. Seeking the possible neural correlates of ubiquitous temporal awareness, this article reexamines fMRI data from off-task “default mode” periods in 25 healthy subjects studied by Grady et al. , 2005). “Brain reading” using support vector machines detected information specifying elapsed time, and further ana…Read more
  •  65
    Is "Cognitive Neuroscience" an Oxymoron?
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 18 (4): 283-286. 2011.
    Could "cognitive neuroscience" be an oxymoron? "Cognitive" and "neuroscience" cohere only to the extent that the entities identified as "cognitive" can be coordinated with entities identified as neural. This coordination is typically construed as intertheoretic reduction between "levels" of scientific description. On the cognitive side, folk psychological concepts crystallize into behavioral taxonomies, which are further analyzed into purported cognitive capacities. These capacities are expresse…Read more
  •  63
    Commentary on Searle and the 'Deep Unconscious'
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (3): 201-202. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Searle and the ‘Deep Unconscious’”Dan Lloyd (bio)Can another person know my thoughts with better authority than I know them myself? With his affirmative answer to this question, Freud invented the twentieth-century human, a being whose mind is accessible to scrutiny from outside, and whose attempts at conscious self-explanation are at best partial and in many cases wrong. Even as Freud’s scientific influence wanes, the…Read more
  •  84
    Consciousness: A connectionist manifesto (review)
    Minds and Machines 5 (2): 161-85. 1995.
      Connectionism and phenomenology can mutually inform and mutually constrain each other. In this manifesto I outline an approach to consciousness based on distinctions developed by connectionists. Two core identities are central to a connectionist theory of consciouness: conscious states of mind are identical to occurrent activation patterns of processing units; and the variable dispositional strengths on connections between units store latent and unconscious information. Within this broad frame…Read more
  •  78
    Terra cognita: From functional neuroimaging to the map of the mind (review)
    Brain and Mind 1 (1): 93-116. 2000.
    For more than a century the paradigm inspiringcognitive neuroscience has been modular and localist.Contemporary research in functional brain imaginggenerally relies on methods favorable to localizingparticular functions in one or more specific brainregions. Meanwhile, connectionist cognitive scientistshave celebrated the computational powers ofdistributed processing, and pioneered methods forinterpreting distributed representations. This papertakes a connectionist approach to functionalneuroimag…Read more
  •  36
    Popping the thought balloon
    In Don Ross, Andrew Brook & David L. Thompson (eds.), Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment, Mit Press. pp. 169--99. 2000.
    Many recovering dualists find that the old Cartesian demons are hard to exorcise. Dual substance abuse manifests itself not only as metaphysical dualism, but as a pervasive epistemological framework that creates an unhealthy codependent relationship between scientific realism and phenomenology. Daniel Dennett has led philosophers to recognize many of the symptoms of creeping crypto Cartesianism. In this paper, I try to take Dennett to the limit: Descartes lives on, I argue, in the very heart of …Read more
  •  92
    Mental representation from the bottom up
    Synthese 70 (January): 23-78. 1987.
    Commonsense psychology and cognitive science both regularly assume the existence of representational states. I propose a naturalistic theory of representation sufficient to meet the pretheoretical constraints of a "folk theory of representation", constraints including the capacities for accuracy and inaccuracy, selectivity of proper objects of representation, perspective, articulation, and "efficacy" or content-determined functionality. The proposed model states that a representing device is a d…Read more
  •  25
    Double trouble for gestalt bubbles
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (4): 417-418. 2003.
    The “Gestalt Bubble” model of Lehar is not supported by the evidence offered. The author invalidly concludes that spatial properties in experience entail an explicit volumetric spatial representation in the brain. The article also exaggerates the extent to which phenomenology reveals a completely three-dimensional scene in perception.