•  1
    I
    In Samuel Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell. 2017.
    What is the relation between mind and physical reality? Well‐established schools of thought give starkly opposing answers to this question. Descartes insisted that mental phenomena are non‐physical in nature. This view seems inviting because mental phenomena are indisputably different from everything else. Moreover, it's safe to assume that all phenomena that aren't mental have some physical nature. So it may seem that the best way to explain how the mental differs from everything else is to hyp…Read more
  •  65
    Res Cogitans: An Essay in Rational Psychology (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 73 (9): 240-252. 1976.
  •  10
    Memory (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 66 (1): 17-22. 1969.
  •  19
    The Nature of Consciousness
    Mind 113 (451): 581-588. 2004.
  •  67
    The nature of mental imagery: How null is the “null hypothesis”?
    with Gianfranco Dalla Barba
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (2): 187-188. 2002.
    Is mental imagery pictorial? In Pylyshyn's view no empirical data provides convincing support to the “pictorial” hypothesis of mental imagery. Phenomenology, Pylyshyn says, is deeply deceiving and offers no explanation of why and how mental imagery occurs. We suggest that Pylyshyn mistakes phenomenology for what it never pretended to be. Phenomenological evidence, if properly considered, shows that mental imagery may indeed be pictorial, though not in the way that mimics visual perception. Moreo…Read more
  • Thinking that one thinks
    In Alex Burri (ed.), Language and thought, Walter De Gruyter. 1997.
  •  269
    The extra ingredient
    Biology and Philosophy 36 (2): 1-4. 2021.
    Birch et. al. see their model as incompatible with higher-order-thought (HOT) theories of consciousness, on which a state is conscious if one is in some suitable way aware of that state. They see higher-order (HO) awareness as an “extra ingredient”. But since Birch et al go on to say that “[t]his is not the place for a detailed discussion of HOT theories,” they don’t address why they take HO awareness to be an extra ingredient or why HOT theorists are convinced that it’s needed. In this comme…Read more
  •  36
    Chalmers' Meta-Problem
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 (9-10): 194-204. 2019.
    There is strong reason to doubt that the intuitions Chalmers' meta-problem focuses on are widespread or independent of proto-theoretical prompting. So it's unlikely that they result from factors connected to the nature of consciousness. In any case, it's only the accuracy of the problem intuitions that matters for evaluating theories of consciousness or revealing the nature of consciousness, not an explanation of how they arise. Unless we determine that they're accurate about consciousness, we m…Read more
  • Higher-order Theories of Consciousness
    In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  42
    The Disappearance of Introspection (review)
    Philosophical Review 101 (2): 425. 1992.
  •  17
    Memory (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 66 (1): 17-22. 1969.
  •  93
    Dintre fenomenele mentale, nici unul nu pare să reziste atât de bine explicaţiei precum conştiinţa. Parţial, dificultatea se datorează faptului că folosim termenul „conştient” şi alţii înrudiţi să dea seama de anumite fenomene distincte ale căror legături nu sunt întotdeauna clare. Iar acest lucru duce adesea la amestecarea acestor fenomene distincte. De aceea, orice încercare de a explica conştiinţa trebuie să înceapă prin a distinge diferitele lucruri pe care le numim conştiinţă. Un astfel de …Read more
  •  19
    Moore's paradox and Crimmins's case
    Analysis 62 (2): 167-171. 2002.
  •  202
    Quality-space theory in olfaction
    with Benjamin D. Young and Andreas Keller
    Frontiers in Psychology 5. 2014.
    Quality-space theory (QST) explains the nature of the mental qualities distinctive of perceptual states by appeal to their role in perceiving. QST is typically described in terms of the mental qualities that pertain to color. Here we apply QST to the olfactory modalities. Olfaction is in various respects more complex than vision, and so provides a useful test case for QST. To determine whether QST can deal with the challenges olfaction presents, we show how a quality space (QS) could be construc…Read more
  •  23
    XV-Unity of Consciousness and the Self
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (1): 325-352. 2003.
  •  18
    The necessity of foreknowledge
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 1 (1): 22-25. 1976.
  •  22
    Sensory quality and the relocation story
    Philosophical Topics 26 (1-2): 321-50. 1999.
  •  392
    Measuring away an attentional confound?
    with Jorge Morales, Yasha Mouradi, Claire Sergent, Ned Block, Vincent Taschereau-Dumouchel, Piercesare Grimaldi, and Hakwan Lau
    Neuroscience of Consciousness 3 (1): 1-3. 2017.
    A recent fMRI study by Webb et al. (Cortical networks involved in visual awareness independent of visual attention, Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 2016;113:13923–28) proposes a new method for finding the neural correlates of awareness by matching atten- tion across awareness conditions. The experimental design, however, seems at odds with known features of attention. We highlight logical and methodological points that are critical when trying to disentangle attention and awareness.
  •  138
    A striking difference between those fields we classify as humanities and those we regard as sciences is the attitude within each field toward its history. Learning about literature, music, or the visual arts requires becoming knowledgeable about a significant amount of the history of those areas. And education in these fields, at whatever level, invariably involves some study of great accomplishments in the past. By contrast, scientific work and standard scientific textbooks make little referenc…Read more
  •  17
    Applied ethics and ethical theory (edited book)
    with David M. Rosenthal and Fadlou Shehadi
    University of Utah Press. 1988.
  •  140
    Multiple drafts and higher-order thoughts (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (4): 911-18. 1993.
    whatever it is that occurs in between the two. Though superficially tempting, this idea heightens the air of mystery surrounding consciousness. As far..
  •  219
    Consciousness, content, and metacognitive judgments
    Consciousness and Cognition 9 (2): 203-214. 2000.
    Because metacognition consists in our having mental access to our cognitive states and mental states are conscious only when we are conscious of them in some suitable way, metacognition and consciousness shed important theoretical light on one another. Thus, our having metacognitive access to information carried by states that are not conscious helps con?rm the hypothesis that a mental state
  •  93
    Mind-body materialism is at its most inviting in the context of trying to give a unified treatment of the natural world. And the principle challenge it faces is to do justice to the distinguishing features of mental phenomena, which set them off from nonmental, physical reality. This challenge it not easy to meet. In 1971 I suggested that the difficulty in meeting it makes especially appealing the eliminative materialism of Feyerabend and Rorty. If adopting the materialist view that mental pheno…Read more