•  71
    Hegel and Skepticism (review)
    Idealistic Studies 22 (3): 267-269. 1992.
    A book on this topic is long overdue. It is high time that a competent Hegel scholar recognized and assessed the danger posed to Hegel’s whole system by the skeptical tradition, argued that Hegel’s Jena writings, culminating in the Phenomenology, are primarily works of epistemology rather than metaphysics, examined Hegel’s own views on ancient and modern skepticism, identified and criticized Hegel’s own strategies for defending his thought against the skeptical threat, and took Hegel seriously a…Read more
  •  60
    A Few Words from the Associate Editor
    The Owl of Minerva 21 (1): 3-4. 1989.
  •  54
    Presents the basic elements of the philosophy of religion tradition in a new and provocative way as original philosophical narrative interspersed with rich selections from Plato, Boethius, Thomas Aquinas, Anselm, Pascal, Descartes, Paley, Leibniz, Hume, Hegel, Kant, Mill, Stephen, Royce, James, and Clifford. The history and concepts of philosophy of religion emerge more clearly through this integration and interrelation of classical texts with modern summary and interpretation.
  •  50
    Sources of Nietzsche's "God is Dead!" and its Meaning for Heidegger
    Journal of the History of Ideas 45 (2): 263. 1984.
  •  48
    Three Paradigm Theories of Time
    Process Studies 48 (1): 88-104. 2019.
    The three theories considered here, real continuous time, real serial time, and unreal time, are each in some sense a reaction to Hume’s theory of serial or “spatialized” time. Hence, Hume’s theory is elaborated on as a foundation for the discussion and comparison of the subsequent three. This brief excursion into the nature of time may help to illuminate the differences among these three and to suggest some of their possible implications, particularly with regard to the existential difference b…Read more
  •  47
    Hegel’s Theory of Mental Activity (review)
    The Owl of Minerva 26 (2): 224-228. 1995.
    The purpose of this book is the exegesis and criticism of §§ 387-482 of the Encyclopedia. DeVries is skillful at this task, coloring his portrait of subjective spirit with understandings of relevant sections of Hegel’s other texts, notably the Phenomenology and the two Logics. The result is worth reading, for it proves to offer several new and - as the author himself expressly wishes - “controversial” ways of looking at the philosophy of spirit.
  •  46
    From Self-Consciousness to Reason in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit
    International Philosophical Quarterly 53 (3): 309-324. 2013.
    The transition from self-consciousness as the unhappy consciousness to reason as the critique of idealism is among the most important in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Yet this transition is implicit and not readily discernible. This paper investigates (1) whether we can discover and describe any roadblock that the unhappy consciousness is able to knock down, or despite which it is able to maneuver, and so become reason; or (2) whether the unhappy consciousness arrives at an impassable dead en…Read more
  •  46
    Miscellaneous Writings of G. W. F. Hegel (review)
    The Owl of Minerva 37 (2): 191-196. 2006.
    This is the right book done wrong. Stewart has perceived a genuine gap in the published English Hegel translations, but has filled it in a way that does not enhance anglophone Hegel scholarship. He has instead produced a so-called “non-book,” i.e. has only slapped together a bunch of previously published and readily available translations with a new introduction, bibliography, and index. Moreover, he has failed to include many of Hegel’s most important essays and reviews.
  •  45
  •  44
    Five Undergraduate-Level Introductions To Hegel (review)
    The Owl of Minerva 13 (3): 7-10. 1982.
  •  44
    Freiheit und System bei Hegel (review)
    The Owl of Minerva 12 (3): 9-11. 1981.
    One notices immediately that this is a very well organized piece of work, complete with both name and subject indices. The six-page analytic table of contents helpfully distinguishes Angehrn’s various digressions, chiefly into Marxian thought, from the mainstream of his argument. The bibliography is generally an excellent brief sampling of the pertinent Hegelian literature of the last fifteen or twenty years; although, as one might easily expect, since Angehrn earned his doctorate with this work…Read more
  •  42
    Notes
    The Owl of Minerva 10 (1): 10-10. 1978.
  •  41
    A Reply to Professor Williams
    The Owl of Minerva 14 (3): 7-8. 1983.
  •  28
    Dostoevskii's Specific Influence on Nietzsche's Preface to Daybreak
    with Douglas G. Stenberg
    Journal of the History of Ideas 52 (3): 441-461. 1991.
  •  24
    A Few Words from the Associate Editor
    The Owl of Minerva 25 (1): 3-4. 1993.
    Pure serendipity got me involved in the HSA. I was in my first month of graduate school, had already decided to write my M.A. thesis on Hegel, and had begun to study the Philosophy of Right in preparation for this work. Then I learned from a posting on a bulletin board that some outfit called the “Hegel Society of America” - which I had never heard of - was about to have a meeting just two miles down the road. My thesis advisor strongly encouraged me to attend - so I went, but with no idea what …Read more
  •  17
    The Self-Winding Circle (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 17 (3): 79-80. 1985.
  •  16
    This paper argues for the primacy of language over vision as a means of communication. Words convey information more clearly, accurately, reliably, and profoundly than images do. Images by themselves give only impressions; they do not denote, unless accompanied by some sort or level of description. Also, any visual image, whether physical or mental, unless it is eidetic, must involve some degree of interpretation, interpolation, or description for it to be capable of conveying information, havin…Read more
  •  14
    Dark Riddle (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 52 (3): 732-734. 1999.
    Yovel is a prolific, diligent, and sagacious Israeli scholar who has published extensively on Maimonides, Spinoza, Kant, Hegel, and Nietzsche, and who holds named chairs in philosophy at both Hebrew University of Jerusalem and the New School for Social Research. That such a prominent Jewish intellectual has created a perceptive book-length analysis of an important topic which frequently inspires articles and books by non-Jews is a welcome addition to the literature on German philosophy. It is al…Read more
  •  14
    Self and World in Schopenhauer’s Philosophy (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 23 (2): 138-139. 1991.
  •  13
  •  7
    Thinking in the Light of Time (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 54 (4): 911-913. 2001.
    This is a lucid and ambitious book. It is about Heidegger, not Hegel. Boer recognizes that her “wide-ranging” endeavor to “give a systematic interpretation of Heidegger’s entire thinking” is a difficult project that “entails risks”. She meets the challenge head on, considering not only the usually expected texts in Heidegger’s corpus, but also devoting “considerable attention to texts that have only been available for a few years”.
  •  7
    Ernst Cassirer (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 54 (4): 921-923. 2001.
    Lofts’s purpose is to interpret Cassirer in the light of francophone post-structuralist thought, particularly that of Jacques Lacan. Portraying a cautious neo-Kantian as a proto-post-structuralist may seem almost perverse, but the notion has potential. Unfortunately, the book reads as if it were still in rough draft. Its sections are disconnected, its arguments and insights are truncated or aphoristic, its style is careless, and it is poorly edited. Orthographical and typographical errors abound…Read more
  •  5
    Metaphysics to Metafictions: Hegel, Nietzsche, and the End of Philosophy (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 53 (2): 463-464. 1999.
    Miklowitz’s central historical thesis is that Hegel’s “bold claims of metaphysics were burst into fragments under blows from Nietzsche’s hammer”. This thesis fails to account for the many profitable readings of Hegel as an epistemologist rather than a metaphysician. In Miklowitz’s reading, Hegel seems to fit the Schopenhauerian caricature of the pompous Schwabian concocting “grandiose... hubristic” pretensions to absolute knowledge “that would have made even Faust blush”.