-
592Tetens’ Refutation of Idealism and Properly Basic BeliefIn Gideon Stiening & Udo Thiel (eds.), Johann Nikolaus Tetens : Philosophie in der Tradition des Europäischen Empirismus, De Gruyter. pp. 147-168. 2014.
-
Hume on Pyrrhonian Scepticism and Suspension of JudgementIn Scott Stapleford & Verena Wagner (eds.), Hume and contemporary epistemology. 2024.This paper examines Hume’s understanding of a third doxastic position distinct from belief and disbelief, arguing that his epistemology presupposes different forms of doxastic neutrality. While Hume does not explicitly discuss this third position, his Treatise of Human Nature and Enquiry concerning Human Understanding offer ideas relevant to contemporary debates on suspension of judgement and inquiry. Hume engaged with Pyrrhonian scepticism, finding its suspension of judgement excessive, yet ack…Read more
-
21Hume and contemporary epistemology (edited book)This is the first edited collection dedicated to demonstrating Hume's relevance to contemporary debates in epistemology. It features original essays by Hume scholars and epistemologists that address a wide range of important questions, including: What does a Humean conception of knowledge look like? How do Hume's understanding of belief and suspension of judgement bear on current debates about doxastic attitudes? Is there a Humean way of uniting reasons in the epistemic and practical domains? Wh…Read more
-
Evidentialism at 40: New Arguments, New Angles (edited book). 2026.When their landmark paper, “Evidentialism” (1985), first appeared, Conee and Feldman expressed some surprise that the theory needed any defense at all. But the need for a defense has become increasingly apparent in the last forty years as a wide variety of non-evidentialist epistemologies have emerged. The initial paper was the launching point for an enormous research program in epistemology—many epistemologists define their points of view at least partly in terms of how they relate to evidentia…Read more
-
Appearances and the Problem of Stored BeliefsIn Kevin McCain, Scott Stapleford & Matthias Steup (eds.), Seemings: New Arguments, New Angles, Routledge. 2023.Internalist theories of epistemic justification supposedly have trouble explaining what justifies beliefs that are both stored in memory and currently out of mind. This is the problem of stored beliefs. This chapter provides a preliminary defence of stored/dispositional appearances and suggests that they provide a straightforward solution to the problem of stored beliefs.
-
97Seemings: New Arguments, New Angles (edited book)Routledge. 2023.This volume presents new research on the epistemology of seemings. It features original essays by leading epistemologists on the nature and epistemic import of seemings and intuitions. Seemings and intuitions are often appealed to in philosophical theorizing. In fact, epistemological theories such as phenomenal conservatism and dogmatism give pride of place to seemings. Such views insist that seemings are of central importance to theories of epistemic justification. However, there are many quest…Read more
-
Epistemic Dilemmas, Epistemic Quasi-Dilemmas, and Quasi-Epistemic DilemmasIn Scott Stapleford & Kevin McCain (eds.), Epistemic Duties: New Arguments, New Angles. 2020.In this paper we distinguish between epistemic dilemmas, epistemic quasi-dilemmas, and quasi epistemic dilemmas. Our starting point is the commonsense position that S faces a genuine dilemma only when S must take one of two paths and both are bad. It’s the “must” that we think is key. Moral dilemmas arise because there are cases where S must perform A and S must perform B—where ‘must’ implies a moral duty—but S cannot do both. In such a situation, S is doomed to violate a moral obligation. Analo…Read more
-
51Epistemic Dilemmas: New Arguments, New Angles (edited book)It seems plausible that there can be “no win” moral situations in which no matter what one does one fails some moral obligation. Is there an epistemic analog to moral dilemmas? Are there epistemically dilemmatic situations—situations in which we are doomed to violate an epistemic requirement? If there are, when exactly do they arise and what can we learn from them? A team of top epistemologists address these and closely related questions from a variety of new, sometimes unexpected, angles. Anyon…Read more
-
Kant's Analogy of the SphereIn Valerio Hrsg v. Rohden, Ricardo Terra & Guido Almeida (eds.), Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants, De Gruyter. 2008.
-
Bound by the EvidenceIn Scott Stapleford & Kevin McCain (eds.), Epistemic Duties: New Arguments, New Angles. 2020.An evidentialist can be extreme about epistemic requirements in a couple of different ways. At the reductionist end of the spectrum are those who think our epistemic obligations are fully satisfied by the mere having of evidential fit—where having implies nothing about doing. Your beliefs ought to align with your evidence, in other words, but there’s nothing you’re obligated to do in order to get yourself into the epistemically optimal position. At the expansionist end of the spectrum are those …Read more
-
38Tetens’s Writings on Method, Language, and Anthropology (edited book)Containing all of the key writings leading up to the publication of his Philosophical Essays in 1777, this volume presents complete works by Johann Nicolaus Tetens (1736-1807) in English for the very first time. These important essays focus on method in metaphysics and mathematics, the analysis of language, and various anthropological questions that occupied thinkers of the period. Key features of the volume include: · Accurate, readable translations · Detailed scholarly notes · A substantial…Read more
-
62Epistemic Duties: New Arguments, New Angles (edited book)There are arguably moral, legal, and prudential constraints on behavior. But are there epistemic constraints on belief? Are there any requirements arising from intellectual considerations alone? This volume includes original essays written by top epistemologists that address this and closely related questions from a variety of new, sometimes unexpected, angles. It features a wide variety of positions, ranging from arguments for and against the existence of purely epistemic requirements, reductio…Read more
-
66Logic Works is a critical and extensive introduction to logic. It asks questions about why systems of logic are as they are, how they relate to ordinary language and ordinary reasoning, and what alternatives there might be to classical logical doctrines. It considers how logical analysis can be applied to carefully represent the reasoning employed in academic and scientific work, better understand that reasoning, and identify its hidden premises. Aiming to be as much a reference work and handboo…Read more
-
127Intraspecies impermissivismEpisteme 16 (3): 340-356. 2018.The Uniqueness thesis says that any body of evidence E uniquely determines which doxastic attitude is rationally permissible regarding some proposition P. Permissivists deny Uniqueness. They are charged with arbitrarily favouring one doxastic attitude out of the set of attitudes they regard as rationally permissible. Simpson claims that an appeal to differences in cognitive abilities can remove the arbitrariness. I argue that it can't. Impermissivists face a challenge of their own: The problem o…Read more
-
74Was Berkeley an Extracranialist?Philosophical Forum 50 (2): 225-238. 2019.We defend a ‘tight borders’ view of mind and cognition. Our key move comes from Berkeley.
-
115Believing Against the Evidence: Agency and the Ethics of BeliefPhilosophical Review 126 (4): 551-554. 2017.
-
122The worst argument in the world – defendedThink 16 (47): 15-23. 2017.In this paper, I argue that Berkeley’s master argument is not the worst argument in the world—more like third or fourth.
-
88Completing Epistemic OughtsPhilosophical Forum 45 (2): 133-148. 2014.Our intuitions about what a person epistemically ought or ought not believe are sometimes quite clear. Keith DeRose and Richard Feldman have devised examples about which our intuitions are likely to conflict. DeRose argues that the conflict of intuitions arises from ambiguity in the epistemic ought. I argue that it results from incompleteness. The success of the argument depends on rejecting the narrow conception of evidential support according to which a person’s evidence supports some proposit…Read more
-
52Paul Guyer, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy (review)Philosophy in Review 27 (3): 182. 2007.
-
82A Refutation of Idealism from 1777Idealistic Studies 40 (1-2): 139-146. 2010.The paper identifies a possible precedent for Kant’s Refutation of Idealism in the work of Johann Nicolaus Tetens. An attempt is made to reconstruct the reasoning that led Tetens to reject idealism as a false starting point, and some parallels are drawn between Tetens’s psychologistic approach to the problem andKant’s transcendental methodology.
-
148On the Contradiction in Conception Test of the Categorical ImperativeSouth African Journal of Philosophy 26 (3): 306-318. 2007.The author argues against Christine Korsgaard's influential interpretation of Kant's contradiction in conception test of the categorical imperative. Korsgaard's rejection of the ‘teleological' interpretation is shown to be based on a misunderstanding of the role that teleology plays for Kant in ruling out immoral maxims, and her defence of the ‘practical' interpretation is shown to be less faithful to the text than the competing ‘logical' interpretation. The works of Barbara Herman and Allen Woo…Read more
-
165Why There May Be Epistemic DutiesDialogue 54 (1): 63-89. 2015.Chase Wrenn argues that there are no epistemic duties. When it appears that we have an epistemic duty to believe, disbelieve or suspend judgement about some proposition P, we are really under a moral obligation to adopt the attitude towards P that our evidence favours. The argument appeals to theoretical parsimony: our conceptual scheme will be simpler without epistemic duties and we should therefore drop them. I argue that Wrenn’s strategy is flawed. There may well be things that we ought to do…Read more
-
1Kenneth R. Westphal, Kant's Transcendental Proof of Realism Reviewed by (review)Philosophy in Review 26 (4): 308-310. 2006.
-
158What's the point of a dreaming argument?Think 18 (52): 31-34. 2019.In this paper, I argue that dreaming arguments are no cause for alarm.
-
134Epistemic versus all things considered requirementsSynthese 192 (6): 1861-1881. 2015.Epistemic obligations are constraints on belief stemming from epistemic considerations alone. Booth is one of the many philosophers who deny that there are epistemic obligations. Any obligation pertaining to belief is an all things considered obligation, according to him—a strictly generic, rather than specifically epistemic, requirement. Though Booth’s argument is valid, I will try to show that it is unsound. There are two central premises: S is justified in believing that P iff S is blameless …Read more
-
96Reid, Tetens, and Kant on the External WorldIdealistic Studies 37 (2): 87-104. 2007.Building on the research of Manfred Kuehn, the author argues that, whatever influence the Scottish Common Sense Philosophy of Thomas Reid may have had on the development of Immanuel Kant’s refutation of idealism, it was filtered through the thinking of Kant’s largely forgotten German contemporary, Johann Nicolaus Tetens. While the importance of Tetens for understanding Kant is examined in connection with only one idea, the aim is to demonstrate that Tetens is a figure worthy of serious historica…Read more
-
1807Epistemic duties and failure to understand one’s evidencePrincipia: An International Journal of Epistemology 16 (1): 147-177. 2012.The paper defends the thesis that our epistemic duty is the duty to proportion our beliefs to the evidence we possess. An inclusive view of evidence possessed is put forward on the grounds that it makes sense of our intuitions about when it is right to say that a person ought to believe some proposition P. A second thesis is that we have no epistemic duty to adopt any particular doxastic attitudes. The apparent tension between the two theses is resolved by applying the concept of duty to belief …Read more
-
1Seeing a Flower in the Garden: Common Sense, Transcendental IdealismIn Elizabeth Robinson & Chris W. Surprenant (eds.), Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment, Routledge. 2017.Stapleford (2007) identified Johann Nicolaus Tetens as the missing link between Reid’s common sense treatment of external world scepticism and Kant’s transcendental Refutation of Idealism. While that account is arguably correct, it failed to recognize the distinction between being justified in believing P and being justified in believing that my belief in P is justified. This paper corrects the oversight and explains its implications. Tetens emerges as a weak externalist regarding knowledge of e…Read more
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology |
17th/18th Century Philosophy |
Areas of Interest
Epistemology |
17th/18th Century Philosophy |