Saint Louis University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
College Station, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  20
    Descartes on Immortality and Animals
    The European Legacy 29 (2): 184-198. 2023.
    For Descartes, our minds are not natural causes because they are not themselves objects; rather, they are the activities that identify objects. In short, they are our challenges to the natural order of things, both in how we adapt to novel situations (as exhibited in what has been called the “rational action test”) and in how we respond in unexpected yet appropriate ways to linguistic cues (in the “language test”). Because these tests reveal ways in which our minds (as “pure,” creative, willful,…Read more
  •  17
    George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy
    Oxford University Press. 2021.
    This book is a study of the philosophy of the early 18th century Irish philosopher George Berkeley in the intellectual context of his times, with a particular focus on how, for Berkeley, mind is related to its ideas. It does not assume that thinkers like Descartes, Malebranche, or Locke define for Berkeley the context in which he develops his own thought. Instead, he indicates how Berkeley draws on a tradition that informed his early training and that challenges much of the early modern thought …Read more
  •  58
    Berkeley on God
    In Samuel C. Rickless (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley, Oxford University Press. pp. 177-93. 2022.
    Berkeley’s appeal to a posteriori arguments for God’s existence supports belief only in a God who is finite. But by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. In this latter argument, God is not the efficient cause of particular finite things in the world, for such an explanation does not provide a justification or rationale for why the totality of finite things would exist in the first place. Instead, God is understood as the creator of the total …Read more
  •  9
    The Semiotic Ontology of Jonathan Edwards
    Modern Schoolman 71 (4): 285-304. 1994.
  •  6
    M. Hobbes and America: Exploring the Constitutional Foundations (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-699. 1983.
    Though some of the critical reviews of Frank M. Coleman's Hobbes and America have alluded to the affinities of his work to that of Strauss, Macpherson, Laslett, and Oakeshott, most have ignored Coleman's specifically philosophic treatment of Hobbes as the foundational thinker most responsive to political realities which emerge in the seventeenth century and still characterize American politics. Coleman's purpose is to demonstrate how the operative American constitutional philosophy can be recogn…Read more
  •  32
    Substance and Person: Berkeley on Descartes and Locke
    Ruch Filozoficzny 74 (4): 7. 2018.
    In his post-1720 works, Berkeley focuses his comments about Descartes on mechanism and about Locke on general abstract ideas. He warns against using metaphysical principles to explain observed regularities, and he extends his account to include spiritual substances (including God). Indeed, by calling a substance a spirit, he emphasizes how a person is simply the will that ideas be differentiated and associated in a certain way, not some <i>thing</i> that engages in differentiation. In this sense…Read more
  •  48
    Berkeley's Non-Cartesian Notion of Spiritual Substance
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4): 659-682. 2018.
    As central as the notion of mind is for Berkeley, it is not surprising that what he means by mind stirs debate. At issue are questions about not only what kind of thing a mind is but also how we can know it. This convergence of ontological and epistemological interests in discussing mind has led some commentators to argue that Berkeley's appeal to the Cartesian vocabulary of 'spiritual substance' signals his appropriation of elements of Descartes's theory of mind. But in his account of spiritual…Read more
  •  750
    Berkeley on God's Knowledge of Pain
    In Stefan Storrie (ed.), Berkeley's Three Dialogues: New Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 136-145. 2018.
    Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which would require God to have senses, which he does not). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose identity is intelligible in terms of the int…Read more
  •  38
    Transforming the Hermeneutic Context (review)
    New Vico Studies 8 (n/a): 127-129. 1990.
  •  12
    The Ramist Context of Berkeley's Philosophy
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3): 487-505. 2001.
  •  63
    Berkeley and Spinoza
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 135 (1): 123-134. 2010.
    There is a widespread assumption that Berkeley and Spinoza have little in common, even though early Jesuit critics in France often linked them. Later commentators have also recognized their similarities. My essay focuses on how Berkeley 's comments on the Arnauld-Malebranche debate regarding objective and formal reality and his treatment of god's creation of finite minds within the order of nature relate his theory of knowledge to his doctrine in a way similar to that of Spinoza. On estime souve…Read more
  •  29
    New interpretations of Berkeley's thought (edited book)
    Humanity Books. 2008.
    In this set of previously unpublished essays, noted scholars from North America and Europe describe how the Irish philosopher George Berkeley (1684-1753) continues to inspire debates about his views on knowledge, reality, God, freedom, mathematics, and religion. Here discussions about Berkeley's account of physical objects, minds, and God's role in human experience are resolved within explicitly ethical and theological contexts. This collection uses debates about Berkeley's immaterialism and the…Read more
  •  1312
    How Berkeley Redefines Substance
    Berkeley Studies 24 40-50. 2013.
    In several essays I have argued that Berkeley maintains the same basic notion of spiritual substance throughout his life. Because that notion is not the traditional (Aristotelian, Cartesian, or Lockean) doctrine of substance, critics (e.g., John Roberts, Tom Stoneham, Talia Mae Bettcher, Margaret Atherton, Walter Ott, Marc Hight) claim that on my reading Berkeley either endorses a Humean notion of substance or has no recognizable theory of substance at all. In this essay I point out how my inter…Read more
  •  25
    L'Anthropologie de saint Thomas, ed. N. A. Luyten (review)
    Modern Schoolman 53 (3): 319-319. 1976.
  • Senior Editor’s Note
    Berkeley Studies 18 2. 2007.
  • Book reviews (review)
    with Michael Littleford, Gary Shapiro, and Paul Fairfield
    Man and World 26 (2): 219-235. 1993.
  •  28
    Postmodernity, Poststructuralism, and the Historiography of Modern Philosophy
    International Philosophical Quarterly 35 (3): 255-267. 1995.
    Well-known for its criticism of totalizing accounts of reason and truth, postmodern thought also makes positive contributions to our understanding of the sensual, ideological, and linguistic contingencies that inform modernist representations of self, history, and the world. The positive side of postmodernity includes structuralism and poststructuralism, particularly as expressed by theorists concerned with practices of the body (Lacan, Foucault, Deleuze), commodity differences (Adorno, Althusse…Read more
  • An explanation of how to organize and teach a course in recent continental thought, including treatments of the major figures in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Reprint from *In the Socratic Tradition: Essays on Teaching Philosophy*, ed. Tziporah Kasachkoff (Lanham, Md: Rowman and Littlefield, 1998).
  •  16
    Myth and the Grammar of Discovery in Francis Bacon
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 15 (4). 1982.
  •  1043
    The ramist context of Berkeley's philosophy
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3). 2001.
    Berkeley's doctrines about mind, the language of nature, substance, minima sensibilia, notions, abstract ideas, inference, and freedom appropriate principles developed by the 16th-century logician Peter Ramus and his 17th-century followers (e.g., Alexander Richardson, William Ames, John Milton). Even though Berkeley expresses himself in Cartesian or Lockean terms, he relies on a Ramist way of thinking that is not a form of mere rhetoric or pedagogy but a logic and ontology grounded in Stoicism. …Read more
  •  11
    Contemporary Continental Thought
    Prentice-Hall. 2004.
    A survey with readings in critical theory, hermeneutics, structuralism, deconstruction, psychoanalytic feminism, poststructuralism, postcolonialism, and postmodernism. Aimed at students and scholars interested in an overview of movements in continental philosophy in the past century.
  •  36
    The Narrative Character of Myth and Philosophy in Vico
    International Studies in Philosophy 20 (1): 1-9. 1988.
  •  45
    Edwards, Berkeley, and Ramist Logic
    Idealistic Studies 31 (1): 55-72. 2001.
    I will suggest that we can begin to see why Edwards and Berkeley sound so much alike by considering how both think of minds or spiritual substances notas things modeled on material bodies but as the acts by which things are identified. Those acts cannot be described using the Aristotelian subject-predicatelogic on which the metaphysics of substance, properties, attributes, or modes is based because subjects, substances, etc. are themselves initially distinguishedthrough such acts. To think of mi…Read more