•  248
    The iterative conception of set
    Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1): 97-110. 2008.
    The phrase ‘The iterative conception of sets’ conjures up a picture of a particular settheoretic universe – the cumulative hierarchy – and the constant conjunction of phrasewith-picture is so reliable that people tend to think that the cumulative hierarchy is all there is to the iterative conception of sets: if you conceive sets iteratively, then the result is the cumulative hierarchy. In this paper, I shall be arguing that this is a mistake: the iterative conception of set is a good one, for al…Read more
  •  246
    ZF + "every set is the same size as a wellfounded set"
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (1): 1-4. 2003.
    Let ZFB be ZF + "every set is the same size as a wellfounded set". Then the following are true. Every sentence true in every (Rieger-Bernays) permutation model of a model of ZF is a theorem of ZFB. (i.e.. ZFB is the theory of Rieger-Bernays permutation models of models of ZF) ZF and ZFAFA are both extensions of ZFB conservative for stratified formulæ. The class of models of ZFB is closed under creation of Rieger-Bernays permutation models
  •  73
    A Note on Freedom from Detachment in the Logic of Paradox
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (1): 15-20. 2013.
    We shed light on an old problem by showing that the logic LP cannot define a binary connective $\odot$ obeying detachment in the sense that every valuation satisfying $\varphi$ and $(\varphi\odot\psi)$ also satisfies $\psi$ , except trivially. We derive this as a corollary of a more general result concerning variable sharing
  •  71
    An Order-Theoretic Account of Some Set-Theoretic Paradoxes
    with Thierry Libert
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 52 (1): 1-19. 2011.
    We present an order-theoretic analysis of set-theoretic paradoxes. This analysis will show that a large variety of purely set-theoretic paradoxes (including the various Russell paradoxes as well as all the familiar implementations of the paradoxes of Mirimanoff and Burali-Forti) are all instances of a single limitative phenomenon
  •  62
    Implementing Mathematical Objects in Set Theory
    Logique Et Analyse 50 (197): 79-86. 2007.
    In general little thought is given to the general question of how to implement mathematical objects in set theory. It is clear that—at various times in the past—people have gone to considerable lengths to devise implementations with nice properties. There is a litera- ture on the evolution of the Wiener-Kuratowski ordered pair, and a discussion by Quine of the merits of an ordered-pair implemen- tation that makes every set an ordered pair. The implementation of ordinals as Von Neumann ordinals i…Read more
  •  58
    NF at (nearly) 75
    Logique Et Analyse 53 (212): 483. 2010.
  •  55
  •  53
    End-extensions preserving power set
    with Richard Kaye
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1): 323-328. 1991.
    We consider the quantifier hierarchy of Takahashi [1972] and show how it gives rise to reflection theorems for some large cardinals in ZF, a new natural subtheory of Zermelo's set theory, a potentially useful new reduction of the consistency problem for Quine's NF, and a sharpening of another reduction of this problem due to Boffa.
  •  46
    Finite-to-one maps
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (4): 1251-1253. 2003.
    It is shown in ZF (without choice) that if there is a finite-to-one map P(X) → X, then X is finite
  •  40
    Decidable Fragments of the Simple Theory of Types with Infinity and $mathrm{NF}$
    with Anuj Dawar and Zachiri McKenzie
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (3): 433-451. 2017.
    We identify complete fragments of the simple theory of types with infinity and Quine’s new foundations set theory. We show that TSTI decides every sentence ϕ in the language of type theory that is in one of the following forms: ϕ=∀x1r1⋯∀xkrk∃y1s1⋯∃ylslθ where the superscripts denote the types of the variables, s1>⋯>sl, and θ is quantifier-free, ϕ=∀x1r1⋯∀xkrk∃y1s⋯∃ylsθ where the superscripts denote the types of the variables and θ is quantifier-free. This shows that NF decides every stratified se…Read more
  •  38
    A Consistent Higher-Order Theory Without a Model
    Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35 (5): 385-386. 1989.
  •  37
    Ramsey’s theorem and König’s Lemma
    with J. K. Truss
    Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (1): 37-42. 2007.
    We consider the relation between versions of Ramsey’s Theorem and König’s Infinity Lemma, in the absence of the axiom of choice
  •  37
    Sharvy’s Lucy and Benjamin Puzzle
    Studia Logica 90 (2). 2008.
    Sharvy’s puzzle concerns a situation in which common knowledge of two parties is obtained by repeated observation each of the other, no fixed point being reached in finite time. Can a fixed point be reached?
  •  31
    Many mathematical objects arise from equivalence classes and invite implementation as those classes. Set-existence principles that would enable this are incompatible with ZFC's unrestricted aussonderung but there are set theories which admit more instances than does ZF. NF provides equivalence classes for stratified relations only. Church's construction provides equivalence classes for “low” sets, and thus, for example, a set of all ordinals. However, that set has an ordinal in turn which is not…Read more
  •  31
    Non-well-foundedness of well-orderable power sets
    with J. K. Truss
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (3): 879-884. 2003.
    Tarski [5] showed that for any set X, its set w(X) of well-orderable subsets has cardinality strictly greater than that of X, even in the absence of the axiom of choice. We construct a Fraenkel-Mostowski model in which there is an infinite strictly descending sequence under the relation |w (X)| = |Y|. This contrasts with the corresponding situation for power sets, where use of Hartogs' ℵ-function easily establishes that there can be no infinite descending sequence under the relation |P(X)| = |Y|
  •  27
    It is shown that, according to NF, many of the assertions of ordinal arithmetic involving the T-function which is peculiar to NF turn out to be equivalent to the truth-in-certain-permutation-models of assertions which have perfectly sensible ZF-style meanings, such as: the existence of wellfounded sets of great size or rank, or the nonexistence of small counterexamples to the wellfoundedness of ∈. Everything here holds also for NFU if the permutations are taken to fix all urelemente
  •  25
    Permutations and stratified formulae a preservation theorem
    Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (5): 385-388. 1990.
  •  20
    Reasoning About Theoretical Entities
    World Scientific. 2003.
    As such this book fills a void in the philosophical literature and presents a challenge to every would-be (anti-)reductionist.
  •  15
    Ramsey’s theorem and König’s Lemma
    with J. K. Truss
    Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (1): 37-42. 2007.
    We consider the relation between versions of Ramsey’s Theorem and König’s Infinity Lemma, in the absence of the axiom of choice.
  •  15
    Sharvy’s Lucy and Benjamin Puzzle
    Studia Logica 90 (2): 249-256. 2008.
    Sharvy’s puzzle concerns a situation in which common knowledge of two parties is obtained by repeated observation each of the other, no fixed point being reached in finite time. Can a fixed point be reached?
  •  15
    Many mathematical objects arise from equivalence classes and invite implementation as those classes. Set-existence principles that would enable this are incompatible with ZFC's unrestricted _aussonderung_ but there are set theories which admit more instances than does ZF. NF provides equivalence classes for stratified relations only. Church's construction provides equivalence classes for "low" sets, and thus, for example, a set of all ordinals. However, that set has an ordinal in turn which is n…Read more
  •  15
    Quine's new foundations
    Journal of Symbolic Logic. 1985.
  •  13
    A Consistent Higher‐Order Theory Without a (Higher‐Order) Model
    Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (5): 385-386. 1989.
  •  10
    Permutations and stratified formulae a preservation theorem
    Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (5): 385-388. 1990.
  •  9
    Erdös-Rado without Choice
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3). 2007.
    A version of the Erdös-Rado theorem on partitions of the unordered n-tuples from uncountable sets is proved, without using the axiom of choice. The case with exponent 1 is just the Sierpinski-Hartogs' result that $\aleph (\alpha)\leq 2^{2^{2^{\alpha}}}$