•  46
    Book reviews (review)
    with George R. Carlson, V. Vuckovic, John Heil, Rex Martin, Colin McGinn, Gerhard D. Wassermann, R. T. Green, and Barbara Von Eckardt
    Philosophia 11 (3-4): 553-560. 1982.
  • Vägledning till Hägerströmstudiet
    Almqvist & Wiksell. 1994.
  •  13
    Law as Fact (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 22 (87): 179-180. 1972.
  • Book reviews (review)
    with George R. Carlson, V. Vuckovic, John Heil, Rex Martin, Colin McGinn, Gerhard D. Wassermann, R. T. Green, and Barbara Von Eckardt
    Philosophia 11 (3-4): 361-428. 1982.
  •  9
    Dieter Lang. Wertung und Erkenntnis (review)
    Perspektiven der Philosophie 8 367-369. 1982.
  • Rätten att handla orätt
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 3. 1993.
  •  28
    Natural law and natural rights
    In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century, Oxford University Press. pp. 472. 2013.
    This chapter, which analyzes the conception of natural laws and natural rights in Great Britain during the seventeenth century, suggests that the widely held belief that rights depend for their existence on being granted by law is not true, and that the opposite is arguably closer to the truth. It also explores the writings on politics and religion during this period that mentioned natural laws and rights.
  •  51
    Featuring hundreds of entries, this authoritative, A-to-Z reference encompasses the full spectrum and history of Western philosophy, covering such topics as logic, metaphysics, ethics, and epistemology, as well as providing incisive profiles of the world's great philosophers, past and present, and their influence. Original.
  •  44
    Flaws in laws
    Philosophical Review 82 (1): 83-98. 1973.
    Statements to the effect that a certain law exists are generally considered to be statements of certain contingent, empirical facts. We will discuss a particular view of this kind-namely, legal positivism'-as presented by G.H. von Wright in Norm and Action.2 Statements to the effect that a certain law exists are also generally considered to obey the laws of deontic logic. This is also von Wright's view. The combination of these two views creates problems. These become particularly conspic…Read more
  •  6
    From Theonomy to Autonomy (review)
    Philosophical Books 40 (3): 159-169. 1999.
    Book reviewed in this article:J.B. Schneewind, The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy.
  •  6
    Adam Smith Reviewed
    Philosophical Books 34 (4): 229-231. 1993.
  •  15
    Problems for anti-expressivism
    Analysis 60 (2): 196-201. 2000.
  •  1
    Locke's Own
    Locke Studies 25. 1994.
  •  16
    From Theonomy to Autonomy
    Philosophical Books 40 (3): 159-169. 1999.
    Book reviewed in this article:J.B. Schneewind, The Invention of Autonomy: A History of Modern Moral Philosophy
  •  79
    How Rights Became “Subjective”
    Ratio Juris 26 (1): 111-132. 2013.
    What is commonly called a right has since about 1980 increasingly come to be called a subjective right. In this paper the origin and rise of this solecism is investigated. Its use can result in a lack of clarity and even confusion. Some aspects of rights-concepts and their history are also discussed. A brief postscript introduces Leibniz's Razor
  • The Absent-Minded Legislator
    Logique Et Analyse 14 (53): 105. 1971.
  •  22
    Dieter Lang. Wertung und Erkenntnis
    Perspektiven der Philosophie 8 (n/a): 367-369. 1982.
  •  37
    Natural Rights in Locke
    Philosophical Topics 12 (3): 73-77. 1981.
  •  4
    Hutcheson: Two Texts on Human Nature (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1993.
    Francis Hutcheson was the first major philosopher of the Scottish Enlightenment, and one of the great thinkers in the history of British moral philosophy. He firmly rejected the reductionist view, common then as now, that morality is nothing more than the prudent pursuit of self-interest, arguing in favour of a theory of a moral sense. The two texts presented here are the most eloquent expressions of this theory. The Reflections on our Common Systems of Morality insists on the connection between…Read more
  • TRIGG, R.: "Reason and Commitment" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 52 (n/a): 185. 1974.
  •  34
    Some Myth about Realism
    Ratio Juris 23 (3): 411-427. 2010.
    This paper discusses the place of philosophical naturalism in the philosophy of law, with special reference to Scandinavian Realism. Hägerström originated a non-cognitivist analysis of certain fundamental legal concepts, but he also proposed an error theory. The two approaches are incompatible, but were not always clearly distinguished. Among his followers, Olivecrona and Ross gradually abandoned the latter, at least from the late 1940s. Many accounts of their views are unclear, because the pres…Read more
  •  25
    Aquinas's Third Way
    American Philosophical Quarterly 6 (4). 1969.
  • PALLADINI, F.-La Biblioteca di Samuel Pufendorf
    Philosophical Books 42 (1): 58-58. 2001.
  •  51
    Locke on Original Appropriation
    American Philosophical Quarterly 19 (3). 1982.
  •  42
    Grotius and the Skeptics
    Journal of the History of Ideas 66 (4): 577-601. 2005.
  •  9
    Human rights Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller & Jeffrey Paul (review)
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (1): 133. 1986.
  •  25
    Two dualisms
    Journal of Value Inquiry 29 (2): 181-185. 1995.
    A discussion of a view proposed by Anthony Kenny, that inferences from factual statements to evaluative or normative statements, are in fact as unproblematic as the commonly accepted inferences inferences in the reverse direction,i. i. i from evaluative or normative statements to factual ones, The paper draws attention to some difficulties inherent in Kenny's view.