•  4
    11 The Future State and the Signs of Desire
    In Manuel Fasko & Peter West (eds.), Berkeley’s Doctrine of Signs, De Gruyter. pp. 211-226. 2024.
  •  15
    Locke and Leibniz on Substance (edited book)
    with Paul Lodge
    Routledge. 2015.
    Locke and Leibniz on Substance gathers together papers by an international group of academic experts, examining the metaphysical concept of substance in the writings of these two towering philosophers of the early modern period. Each of these newly-commissioned essays considers important interpretative issues concerning the role that the notion of substance plays in the work of Locke and Leibniz, and its intersection with other key issues, such as personal identity. Contributors also consider th…Read more
  •  303
    Causation and Modern Philosophy (edited book)
    Routledge. 2010.
    This volume brings together a collection of new essays by leading scholars on the subject of causation in the early modern period, from Descartes to Lady Mary Shepherd. Aimed at researchers, graduate students and advanced undergraduates, the volume advances the understanding of early modern discussions of causation, and situates these discussions in the wider context of early modern philosophy and science. Specifically, the volume contains essays on key early modern thinkers, such as Descartes, …Read more
  •  31
    The Subtraction Argument for the Possibility of Free Mass
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1): 50-57. 2009.
    Jonathan Schaffer has recently argued that there can be objects having only mass. We show that his argument is either invalid or question begging.
  •  149
  •  74
    The subtraction argument for the possibility of free mass
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (1): 50-57. 2009.
    Could an object have only mass and no other property? In giving an affirmative answer to this question, Jonathan Schaffer (2003, pp. 136-8) proposes what he calls ‘the subtraction argument’ for ‘the possibility of free mass’. In what follows, we aim to assess the cogency of this argument in comparison with an argument of the same general form which has also been termed a subtraction argument, namely, Thomas Baldwin’s (1996) subtraction argument for metaphysical nihilism, which is the claim that …Read more
  •  127
    Justifying metaphysical nihilism: A response to Cameron
    Philosophical Quarterly 59 (234): 132-137. 2009.
    Ross Cameron charges the subtraction argument for metaphysical nihilism with equivocation: each premise is plausible only under different interpretations of 'concrete'. This charge is ungrounded; the argument is both valid and supported by basic modal intuitions.
  •  202
    Is metaphysical nihilism interesting?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (2): 210-231. 2009.
    Suppose nothing exists. Then it is true that nothing exists. What makes that true? Nothing! So it seems that if nothing existed, then the principle that every truth is made true by something (the truthmaker principle) would be false. So if it is possible that nothing exists, a claim often called 'metaphysical nihilism', then the truthmaker principle is not necessary. This paper explores various ways to resolve this conflict without restricting metaphysical nihilism in such a way that it would be…Read more
  •  132
    Combinatorialism and the possibility of nothing
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (2). 2006.
    We argue that Armstrong's Combinatorialism allows for the possibility of nothing by giving a Combinatorial account of the empty world and show that such an account is consistent with the ontological and conceptual aims of the theory. We then suggest that the Combinatorialist should allow for this possibility given some methodological considerations. Consequently, rather than being 'spoils for the victor', as Armstrong maintains, deciding whether there might have been nothing helps to determine w…Read more
  •  185
    What is the principle of recombination?
    Dialectica 62 (4): 483-494. 2008.
    In this paper, we give a precise characterization of the principle of recombination and argue that it need not be subject to any restrictions.
  •  12
    Berkeley and the „Principles of Human Knowledge“
    Filosoficky Casopis 53 (445): 146-148. 2005.
  •  86
    Action, knowledge and embodiment in Berkeley and Locke
    Philosophical Explorations 21 (1): 41-59. 2018.
    Embodiment is a fact of human existence which philosophers should not ignore. They may differ to a great extent in what they have to say about our bodies, but they have to take into account that for each of us our body has a special status, it is not merely one amongst the physical objects, but a physical object to which we have a unique relation. While Descartes approached the issue of embodiment through consideration of sensation and imagination, it is more directly reached by consideration of…Read more
  • Causation and Modern Philosophy (edited book)
    with Kenneth Allen
    Routledge. 2011.
  •  18
    Self-knowledge
    In Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Wolenski (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology, Kluwer Academic. pp. 647--672. 2004.
  •  24
    Comment on Davies: A general dilemma?
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 92 225-231. 1992.
    Tom Stoneham; Comment on Davies: A General Dilemma?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 92, Issue 1, 1 June 1992, Pages 225–232, https://doi.org/10.
  •  9
    Transparency, Sense and Self-Knowledge
    In Petr Kotatko & John Biro (eds.), Frege: Sense and Reference One Hundred Years Later, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 103--112. 1995.
  •  71
    On equivocation
    Philosophy 78 (4): 515-519. 2003.
    Equivocation is often described as a fallacy. In this short note I argue that it is not a logical concept but an epistemic one. The argument of one who equivocates is not logically flawed, but it is unpersuasive in a very distinctive way.
  •  1
    Berkeley’s World: An Examination of the Three Dialogues
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (217): 629-631. 2004.
  •  107
    A neglected account of perception
    Dialectica 62 (3): 307-322. 2008.
    I aim to draw the reader's attention to an easily overlooked account of perception, namely that there are no perceptual experiences, that to perceive something is to stand in an external, purely non-Leibnizian relation to it. I introduce the Purely Relational account of perception by discussing a case of it being overlooked in the writings of G.E. Moore, though we also find the same move in J. Cook Wilson, so it has nothing to do with an affection for sense-data. I then discuss the relation betw…Read more
  •  493
    Time and truth: The presentism-eternalism debate
    Philosophy 84 (2): 201-218. 2009.
    There are many questions we can ask about time, but perhaps the most fundamental is whether there are metaphysically interesting differences between past, present and future events. An eternalist believes in a block universe: past, present and future events are all on an equal footing. A gradualist believes in a growing block: he agress with the eternalist about the past and the present but not about the future. A presentist believes that what is present has a special status. My first claim is t…Read more
  •  83
    Boghossian on empty natural kind concepts
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99 (1): 119-22. 1999.
    Paul Boghossian has argued that Externalism is incompatible with privileged self-knowledge because (i) the Externalist can cite no property to be the reference of an empty natural kind concept such as the ether; (ii) without reference there is no content; hence (iii) either we do know on the basis of introspection alone whether an apparent natural kind thought has content or not, in which case we can infer from self-knowledge and a priori knowledge of Externalism alone to the existence in our en…Read more
  •  34
    When did Collier read Berkeley?
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (2). 2007.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  29
    Philosophical Papers Vol.32(2) 2003: 149-155