•  1131
    Religious Epistemology
    Philosophy Compass 10 (8): 547-559. 2015.
    Religious epistemology is the study of how subjects' religious beliefs can have, or fail to have, some form of positive epistemic status and whether they even need such status appropriate to their kind. The current debate is focused most centrally upon the kind of basis upon which a religious believer can be rationally justified in holding certain beliefs about God and whether it is necessary to be so justified to believe as a religious believer ought. Engaging these issues are primarily three g…Read more
  •  1013
    Alvin Plantinga theorizes the existence of a sensus divinitatis – a special cognitive faulty or mechanism dedicated to the production and non-inferential justification of theistic belief. Following Chris Tucker, we offer an evidentialist-friendly model of the sensus divinitatis whereon it produces theistic seemings that non-inferentially justify theistic belief. We suggest that the sensus divinitatis produces these seemings by tacitly grasping support relations between the content of ordinary ex…Read more
  •  846
    Natural Theology, Evidence, and Epistemic Humility
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (2): 19-42. 2017.
    One not infrequently hears rumors that the robust practice of natural theology reeks of epistemic pride. Paul Moser’s is a paradigm of such contempt. In this paper we defend the robust practice of natural theology from the charge of epistemic pride. In taking an essentially Thomistic approach, we argue that the evidence of natural theology should be understood as a species of God’s general self-revelation. Thus, an honest assessment of that evidence need not be prideful, but can be an act of epi…Read more
  •  537
    Evil and the problem of anomaly
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 5 49-87. 2014.
  •  526
    Zagzebski, Authority, and Faith
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 6 (4): 47--59. 2014.
    Epistemic Authority is a mature work of a leading epistemologist and philosopher of religion. It is a work primarily in epistemology with applications to religious epistemology. There are obvious applications of the notion of epistemic authority to philosophy of religion. For, on the face of it, the notion of some kind of ”epistemic authority’ may serve as a conceptual anchor for our understanding of faith. Indeed, there is ample historical precedent for this. Faith, says Locke, is ”the assent t…Read more
  •  433
    In this article, we examine in detail the New Atheists' most serious argument for the conclusion that God does not exist, namely, Richard Dawkins's Ultimate 747 Gambit. Dawkins relies upon a strong explanatory principle involving simplicity. We systematically inspect the various kinds of simplicity that Dawkins may invoke. Finding his crucial premises false on any common conception of simplicity, we conclude that Dawkins has not given good reason to think God does not exist.
  •  382
    A user's guide to design arguments
    with Ted Poston
    Religious Studies 44 (1): 99-110. 2008.
    We argue that there is a tension between two types of design arguments-the fine-tuning argument (FTA) and the biological design argument (BDA). The tension arises because the strength of each argument is inversely proportional to the value of a certain currently unknown probability. Since the value of that probability is currently unknown, we investigate the properties of the FTA and BDA on different hypothetical values of this probability. If our central claim is correct this suggests three res…Read more
  •  374
    Fallibilism, epistemic possibility, and concessive knowledge attributions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (1): 123-132. 2008.
    If knowing requires believing on the basis of evidence that entails what’s believed, we have hardly any knowledge at all. Hence the near-universal acceptance of fallibilism in epistemology: if it's true that "we are all fallibilists now" (Siegel 1997: 164), that's because denying that one can know on the basis of non-entailing evidence1is, it seems, not an option if we're to preserve the very strong appearance that we do know many things (Cohen 1988: 91). Hence the significance of concessive kno…Read more
  •  327
    Divine Hiddenness and the Nature of Belief
    with Ted Poston
    Religious Studies 43 (2). 2007.
    In this paper we argue that attention to the intricacies relating to belief illustrate crucial difficulties with Schellenberg's hiddenness argument. This issue has been only tangentially discussed in the literature to date. Yet we judge this aspect of Schellenberg's argument deeply significant. We claim that focus on the nature of belief manifests a central flaw in the hiddenness argument. Additionally, attention to doxastic subtleties provides important lessons about the nature of faith
  •  302
    John Haldane. Reasonable Faith. Routledge, 2010
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3 (1): 239--242. 2011.
  •  302
    Divine Union with and without the Gospel: A Probabilistic Problem of Pluralism
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 11 (1): 135-143. 2019.
  •  210
    Recent Work on the Problem of Evil
    Analysis 71 (3): 560-573. 2011.
  •  202
    Reducing Responsibility: An Evidentialist Account of Epistemic Blame
    European Journal of Philosophy 20 (4): 534-547. 2010.
    Abstract: This paper argues that instances of what are typically called ‘epistemic irresponsibility’ are better understood as instances of moral or prudenial failure. This hypothesis covers the data and is simpler than postulating a new sui generis form of normativitiy. The irresponsibility alleged is that embeded in charges of ‘You should have known better!’ However, I argue, either there is some interest at stake in knowing or there is not. If there is not, then there is no irresponsibility. I…Read more
  •  195
    Further Epistemological Considerations Concerning Skeptical Theism
    Faith and Philosophy 28 (3): 332-340. 2011.
    I defend the position that the appearance of a conflict between common-sense epistemology and skeptical theism remains, even after one fully appreciates the role defeat plays in rational belief. In particular, Matheson’s recent attempt to establish peace is not fully successful.
  •  194
    Evidentialism and its Discontents (edited book)
    Oxford: Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Few concepts have been considered as essential to the theory of knowledge and rational belief as that of evidence. The simplest theory which accounts for this is evidentialism, the view that epistemic justification for belief--the kind of justification typically taken to be required for knowledge--is determined solely by considerations pertaining to one's evidence. In this ground-breaking book, leading epistemologists from across the spectrum challenge and refine evidentialism, sometimes suggest…Read more
  •  188
    The Problem of Evil
    Oxford Bibliographies. 2014.
    This is a reference guide to contemporary work on the problem of evil with Oxford Bibliographies Online.
  •  167
    Epistemological Considerations Concerning Skeptical Theism
    Faith and Philosophy 25 (2): 172-176. 2008.
    The thesis of this short paper is that skeptical theism does not look very plausible from the perspective of a common sense epistemology. A corollary of this isthat anyone who finds common sense epistemology plausible and is attracted to skeptical theism has some work to do to show that they can form a plausiblewhole. The dialectical situation is that to the degree that this argument is a strong one, to that same degree (at least) the theorist who would like to combinecommon sense epistemology w…Read more
  •  160
    Recently, Dylan Dodd (this Journal ) has tried to clear up what he takes to be some of the many confusions surrounding concessive knowledge attributions (CKAs)—i.e., utterances of the form “S knows that p , but it’s possible that q ” (where q entails not- p ) (Rysiew, Noûs 35(4): 477–514, 2001). Here, we respond to the criticisms Dodd offers of the account of the semantics and the sometime-infelicity of CKAs we have given (Dougherty and Rysiew, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78(1): 121…Read more
  •  140
    Reconsidering the parent analogy: unfinished business for skeptical theists
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 72 (1): 17-25. 2012.
    Skeptical theism has as its foundation the thesis that if God permits evil, his reasons for doing so will likely be beyond our ken. The only defense given for this thesis is the Parent Analogy. There is in the literature only one defense of this use of the Parent Analogy and it has never been confronted. I examine it and expose serious flaws, thus exposing a crack in the very foundation of skeptical theism
  •  137
    Fallibilism
    In Duncan Pritchard & Sven Bernecker (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology, Routledge. 2011.
    Fallibilism in epistemology is neither identical to nor unrelated to the ordinary notion of fallibility. In ordinary life we are forced to the conclusion that human beings are prone to error. The epistemological doctrine of fallibilism, though, is about the consistency of holding that humans have knowledge while admitting certain limitations in human ways of knowing. As will be seen, making the content of the basic intuition more precise is both somewhat contentious and the key to an adequate de…Read more
  •  121
    Knowledge happens: Why Zagzebski has not solved the meno problem
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (1): 73-88. 2011.
    I argue that Linda Zagzebski's proposed solution to the Meno Problem faces serious challenges. The Meno Problem, roughly, is how to explain the value that knowledge, as such, has over mere true belief. Her proposed solution is that believings—when thought of more like actions—can have value in virtue of their motivations. This meshes nicely with her theory that knowledge is, essentially, virtuously motivated true belief. Her solution fails because it entails that, necessarily, all knowledge is m…Read more
  •  99
    Experience First
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. pp. 2. 2013.
  •  84
    Reflections on the Deep Connection Between Problems of Evil and Problems of Divine Hiddenness
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (4): 65--84. 2016.
    In the literature on the subject, it is common to understand the problem of divine hiddenness and the problem of evil as distinct problems. Schellenberg and van Inwagen are representative. Such a sharp distinction is not so obvious to me. In this essay, I explore the relationship between the problem of evil and the problem of divine hiddenness.
  •  82
    Naturalism (review)
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2): 344-345. 2011.
  •  66
    Achieving Knowledge (review)
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1): 166-168. 2012.
  •  66
    Epistemic Justification (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 60 (1): 142-143. 2006.
  •  65
    Epistemic Norms (review)
    Analysis 77 (1): 224-232. 2017.
    With 13 essays, the short chapter summary approach will not work for reviewing this book.1 1 The chapters are not broken down into sections, so I can’t select representatives from sections. With not a single bad essay among them, I get no help narrowing it down that way either. I shall, then, focus on the contributions of women and more junior contributors, setting aside the chapters of the editors and others with whom I have fairly close personal connections.
  •  63
    Introduction
    Res Philosophica 90 (2): 125-126. 2013.