•  406
    The father, the son, and the daughter: Sellars, Brandom, and Millikan
    Pragmatics and Cognition 13 (1): 59-71. 2005.
    The positions of Brandom and Millikan are compared with respect to their common origins in the works of Wilfrid Sellars and Wittgenstein. Millikan takes more seriously the “picturing” themes from Sellars and Wittgenstein. Brandom follows Sellars more closely in deriving the normativity of language from social practice, although there are also hints of a possible derivation from evolutionary theory in Sellars. An important claim common to Brandom and Millikan is that there are no representations …Read more
  • The Nicod Lectures book.
  •  450
    Preface by Daniel C. Dennett Beginning with a general theory of function applied to body organs, behaviors, customs, and both inner and outer representations, ...
  •  45
    Reply to Recanati (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3). 2007.
  •  22
    II—Ruth Garrett Millikan: Loosing the Word–Concept Tie
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 85 (1): 125-143. 2011.
    Sainsbury and Tye (2011) propose that, in the case of names and other simple extensional terms, we should substitute for Frege's second level of content—for his senses—a second level of meaning vehicle—words in the language of thought. I agree. They also offer a theory of atomic concept reference—their ‘originalist’ theory—which implies that people knowing the same word have the ‘same concept’. This I reject, arguing for a symmetrical rather than an originalist theory of concept reference, claim…Read more
  •  135
    Reading mother nature's mind
    In Don Ross, Andrew Brook & David L. Thompson (eds.), Dennett's Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment, Mit Press. 2000.
    I try to focus our differences by examining the relation between what Dennett has termed "the intentional stance" and "the design stance." Dennett takes the intentional stance to be more basic than the design stance. Ultimately it is through the eyes of the intentional stance that both human and natural design are interpreted, hence there is always a degree of interpretive freedom in reading the mind, the purposes, both of Nature and of her children. The reason, or at least a reason, is that int…Read more
  • The Jean-Nicod Lectures 2002
  •  72
  • Intensjonalność
    Przeglad Filozoficzny - Nowa Seria 65. 2008.
    (tłum. Katarzyna Paprzycka)
  •  9
    Précis of Language: A Biological Model
    SWIF Philosophy of Mind Review 5 (2). 2006.
  • Chapter 18 of the Nicod book.
  •  89
    On Reading Signs; Some Differences between Us and The Others If there are certain kinds of signs that an animal cannot learn to interpret, that might be for any of a number of reasons. It might be, first, because the animal cannot discriminate the signs from one another. For example, although human babies learn to discriminate human speech sounds according to the phonological structures of their native languages very easily, it may be that few if any other animals are capable of fully grasping t…Read more
  •  293
    Concepts are highly theoretical entities. One cannot study them empirically without committing oneself to substantial preliminary assumptions. Among the competing theories of concepts and categorization developed by psychologists in the last thirty years, the implicit theoretical assumption that what falls under a concept is determined by description () has never been seriously challenged. I present a nondescriptionist theory of our most basic concepts, which include (1) stuffs (gold, milk), (2)…Read more
  •  2
    Contents of the Nicod Lectures book.
  •  1
    The Nicod Lectures book.
  •  303
    Naturalizing intentionality
    In Bernard Elevitch (ed.), The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, Philosopy Documentation Center. pp. 83-90. 2000.
    Brentano was surely mistaken, however, in thinking that bearing a relation to something nonexistent marks only the mental. Given any sort of purpose, it might not get fulfilled, hence might exhibit Brentano's relation, and there are many natural purposes, such as the purpose of one's stomach to digest food or the purpose of one's protective eye blink reflex to keep out the sand, that are not mental, nor derived from anything mental. Nor are stomachs and reflexes "of" or"about" anything. A reply …Read more
  •  30
    Reply to Taylor (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3): 710-715. 2007.
  •  140
    Wings, Spoons, Pills, and Quills
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (4): 191-206. 1999.
  •  236
    Language conventions made simple
    Journal of Philosophy 95 (4): 161-180. 1998.
    At the start of Convention (1969) Lewis says that it is "a platitude that language is ruled by convention" and that he proposes to give us "an analysis of convention in its full generality, including tacit convention not created by agreement." Almost no clause, however, of Lewis's analysis has withstood the barrage of counter examples over the years,1 and a glance at the big dictionary suggests why, for there are a dozen different senses listed there. Left unfettered, convention wanders freely f…Read more
  •  60
    Response to Boyd's commentary
    Philosophical Studies 95 (1-2): 99-102. 1999.
  • the Nicod Lectures book.
  •  30
  •  256
    II—Ruth Garrett Millikan: Loosing the Word–Concept Tie
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 85 (1): 125-143. 2011.
    Sainsbury and Tye (2011) propose that, in the case of names and other simple extensional terms, we should substitute for Frege's second level of content—for his senses—a second level of meaning vehicle—words in the language of thought. I agree. They also offer a theory of atomic concept reference—their ‘originalist’ theory—which implies that people knowing the same word have the ‘same concept’. This I reject, arguing for a symmetrical rather than an originalist theory of concept reference, claim…Read more
  • Pojecia syntetyczne. Filozoficzne rozwazania o kategoryzacji
    Roczniki Filozoficzne 43 (1): 165. 1995.
  • The Jean-Nicod Lectures 2002
  •  23
    Embedded rationality
    In Murat Aydede & P. Robbins (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition, Cambridge University Press. pp. 171--183. 2009.
  •  28
    Of what use categories?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4): 663-664. 1986.