•  114
    Psychopathy and Moral Understanding
    American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (3). 1977.
  •  27
    Desire, Duty and Moral Absolutes
    Philosophy 55 (212). 1980.
    Philosophers have often claimed that the requirements of morality have an absolute and categorical status. Other values may be relative to the agent's ends, other imperatives hypothetical on his desires: their requirements must be justified by relating the action enjoined to the attainment of those ends or desires, and can be avoided by being shown to be incompatible with them. But the requirements of morality bind us whatever our ends or desires might be: they are not to be justified by referen…Read more
  •  17
    Review: Reviews (review)
    Philosophy 57 (222). 1982.
  •  145
    Intention, responsibility and double effect
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (126): 1-16. 1982.
    I discuss a significant distinction between two different applications of the principle of double effect. It serves sometimes to distinguish the intended effects of an action from side-Effects which are "relevant" to it, As providing reasons against it, For which the agent must admit responsibility, And of which he is the intentional agent; and sometimes to distinguish intended effects from side-Effects which are "irrelevant" to the action, As to which the agent denies responsibility and intenti…Read more
  •  7
    Philosophy and the criminal law (edited book)
    with N. E. Simmonds
    Steiner. 1984.
    Tenth annual conference at the University of Manchester, 8th-10th April 1983.
  •  11
    No Title available: New Books (review)
    Philosophy 61 (235): 133-135. 1986.
  •  4
    Aristotelian Courage
    Ratio (Misc.) 29 (1): 2. 1987.
  •  12
    Morality within the Limits of Reason
    Philosophical Books 31 (4): 242-245. 1992.
  •  12
    Punishment
    Dartmouth Publishing Company. 1993.
    This philosophical work on punishment includes coverage of retributivisms, moral education and reform, consequentialism and rights, sentencing and how to make the punishment fit the crime, abolitionism and sociological perspectives.
  •  3
    Attempted homicide
    Legal Theory 1 (2): 149-178. 1995.
  •  25
    Commentary on "Psychopathy, Other-Regarding Moral Beliefs, and Responsibility"
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (4): 283-286. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Psychopathy, Other-Regarding Moral Beliefs, and Responsibility”R. A. Duff (bio)AbstractI make four criticisms of Fields’s account of one type of psychopathy as a responsibility-negating personality disorder which involves an incapacity to form other-regarding moral beliefs. First, his account of what it is to hold moral beliefs (in terms of accepting universal practical principles) actually specifies neither a necessar…Read more
  •  89
    Philosophy and the criminal law: principle and critique (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1998.
    Five pre-eminent legal theorists tackle a range of fundamental questions on the nature of the philosophy of criminal law. Their essays explore the extent to which and the ways in which our systems of criminal law can be seen as rational and principled. The essays discuss some of the principles by which, it is often thought, a system of law should be structured, and they ask whether our own systems are genuinely principled or riven by basic contradictions, reflecting deeper political and social c…Read more
  •  1
    Criminal Attempts
    Law and Philosophy 18 (1): 69-84. 1999.
  •  8
    [Book review] criminal attempts (review)
    Criminal Justice Ethics 18 (1): 52-60. 1999.
  • Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198): 130-133. 2000.
  •  5
    Opinion
    The Philosophers' Magazine 11 8-8. 2000.
  •  29
    Opinion
    The Philosophers' Magazine 11 8-8. 2000.
  • Appendix: Response to Von Hirsch
    In Derek Matravers & Jonathan E. Pike (eds.), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, Routledge, in Association With the Open University. 2002.
  •  11
    Punishment, communication and community
    In Derek Matravers & Jonathan E. Pike (eds.), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, Routledge, in Association With the Open University. 2002.
    The question "What can justify criminal punishment ?" becomes especially insistent at times, like our own, of penal crisis, when serious doubts are raised not only about the justice or efficacy of particular modes of punishment, but about the very legitimacy of the whole penal system. Recent theorizing about punishment offers a variety of answers to that question-answers that try to make plausible sense of the idea that punishment is justified as being deserved for past crimes; answers that try …Read more
  •  58
    Action, the Act Requirement and Criminal Liability
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55 69-103. 2004.
    The slogan that criminal liability requires an ‘act’, or a ‘voluntary act’, is still something of a commonplace in textbooks of criminal law. There are, it is usually added, certain exceptions to this requirement— cases in which liability is in fact, and perhaps even properly, imposed in the absence of such an act: but the ‘act requirement’ is taken to represent a normally minimal necessary condition of criminal liability. Even offences of strict liability, for which no mens rea is required, req…Read more
  •  1
    No more outlaws
    The Philosophers' Magazine 34 61-64. 2006.