•  54
    No more outlaws
    The Philosophers' Magazine 34 (34): 61-64. 2006.
  • Virtue, vice, and criminal liability
    In Colin Patrick Farrelly & Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue jurisprudence, Palgrave-macmillan. 2007.
  • Responsibility and Liability
    In Matthew Kramer, Claire Grant, Ben Colburn & Antony Hatzistavrou (eds.), The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart: Legal, Political and Moral Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  •  81
    Richard Dagger (in this issue) provides perhaps the most persuasive version of a ‘fair play’ theory of criminal punishment, grounded in an attractive liberal republican political theory. But, I argue, his version of the theory still faces serious objections: that its explanation of why some central mala in se are properly criminalised is still distorting, despite his appeal to the burdens of ‘general compliance’; and that it cannot adequately explain (as it should explain) the differential serio…Read more
  •  125
    Theories of criminal law
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  43
    On the basis of a communicative theory of criminal punishment, I show how mercy has a significant but limited role to play in the criminal law—in particular (although not only) in criminal sentencing. Mercy involves an intrusion into the realm of criminal law of values and concerns that are not themselves part of the perspective of criminal law: a merciful sentencer acts beyond the limits of her legal role, on the basis of moral considerations that conflict with the demands of penal justice. Som…Read more
  •  31
    First paragraph: Dangerous driving attracts a maximum penalty of a heavy fine, or in the most serious cases up to six months’ imprisonment; but if it causes death, the maximum penalty is fourteen years’ imprisonment. Careless driving attracts a maximum penalty of a level 4 fine; driving whilst under the influence of drink or drugs attracts a maximum penalty of a level 5 fine and/or up to six months’ imprisonment: but if someone causes death by careless driving when under the influence of drink o…Read more
  •  23
    First paragraph: The awesome range of Heike Jung’s work—over different aspects of criminal law, different jurisdictions and traditions, different disciplines and languages—makes life both easier and harder for contributors to his Festschrift: easier, because one can choose almost any criminal law topic and be confident that it will connect to his work; harder (for those with the British vices of monolingualism and intellectual parochialism), since one’s paper will display the linguistic, jurisdi…Read more
  •  452
    Legal and moral responsibility
    Philosophy Compass 4 (6): 978-986. 2009.
    The paper begins with the plausible view that criminal responsibility should track moral responsibility, and explains its plausibility. A necessary distinction is then drawn between liability and answerability as two dimensions of responsibility, and is shown to underpin the distinction in criminal law between offences and defences. This enables us to distinguish strict liability from strict answerability, and to see that whilst strict criminal liability seems inconsistent with the principle tha…Read more
  •  49
    I begin by discussing the ways in which a would‐be blamer's own prior conduct towards the person he seeks to blame can undermine his standing to blame her (to call her to account for her wrongdoing). This provides the basis for an examination of a particular kind of ‘bar to trial’ in the criminal law – of ways in which a state or a polity's right to put a defendant on trial can be undermined by the prior misconduct of the state or its officials. The examination of this often neglected legal phen…Read more
  •  101
  •  33
    Preferred Citation: R.A. Duff, Response, Is Accomplice Liability Superfluous?, 156 U. Pa. L. Rev. PENNumbra 444 (2008), http://www.pennumbra.com/responses/04-2008/Duff.pdf
  •  120
    Authority and Responsibility in International Criminal Law
    In Samantha Besson & John Tasioulas (eds.), The Philosophy of International Law, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  96
    Philosophical foundations of criminal law (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Topics covered in this volume include the question of criminalization and the proper scope of the criminal law; the grounds of criminal responsibility; the ways ...
  •  3
    Penal coercion and the apology ritual
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 31 (2): 109-117. 2012.
  •  27
    Preface: The Presumption of Innocence
    with Liz Campbell and James Chalmers
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (2): 283-284. 2014.
    Common lawyers are accustomed to the presumption of innocence being described as a “golden thread” running “[t]hroughout the web” of the criminal law: “that it is the duty of the prosecution to prove the prisoner’s guilt” (Woolmington v DPP [1935] AC 462 per Viscount Sankey LC at 481). But although the language of “golden thread” is memorable and oft-quoted, the presumption of innocence must mean more than this: it is not simply a restatement of the burden of proof in a criminal trial.Once this …Read more
  •  19
    Symposium on Preventive Justice Preface
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (3): 499-500. 2015.
    Ideas of prevention (the prevention of harms, or of wrongs, or of crimes) have always played a significant role in accounts of the proper aims of a system of criminal law, but in recent years they have come to play a more prominent and disturbing part in developments in criminal law policies—most obviously, but by no means only, in the USA and Britain. Governments have sought to meet (or to be seen to be meeting) a range of perceived threats, such as terrorism, organised crime, and various kinds…Read more
  •  19
    How not to Define Punishment
    Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche 5 (1). 2015.
    Download.
  •  62
    In this long-awaited book, Antony Duff offers a new perspective on the structures of criminal law and criminal liability. His starting point is a distinction between responsibility (understood as answerability) and liability, and a conception of responsibility as relational and practice-based. This focus on responsibility, as a matter of being answerable to those who have the standing to call one to account, throws new light on a range of questions in criminal law theory: on the question of crim…Read more
  •  2
    Criminal Attempts
    Oxford University Press UK. 1996.
    This book reflects the belief that a careful study of the Law of Attempts should be both interesting in itself, as well as being a productive route into a number of larger and deeper issues in criminal law theory and in the philosophy of action. By identifying the legal doctrines which courts and legislatures have developed or adopted, the author goes on to ask whether and how they can be rationalized or rendered persuasive. Such an approach involves paying detailed attention to cases. The book …Read more
  •  9
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 104 (413): 211-214. 1995.
  •  52
    Mercy
    In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  156
    Punishment and Crime
    with Ross Harrison
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 139-167. 1988.
  •  10
    Action and Criminal Responsibility
    In O'Connor & C. Sandis (eds.), Blackwell Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Blackwell. pp. 331-7. 2010.
  •  129
    Intentionally Killing the Innocent
    Analysis 34 (1). 1973.