•  216
    Can a Particularist Learn the Difference Between Right and Wrong?
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 1 59-72. 1999.
    This paper is an attempt to answer the charge that extreme moral particularism is unable to explain the possibility of moral concepts and our ability to acquire them. This charge is based on the claim that we acquire moral concepts from experience of instances, and that the sorts of similarities that there must be between the instances are ones that only a generalist can countenance. I argue that this inference is unsound.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 95 (378): 263-265. 1986.
  • Book reviews (review)
    Mind 92 (366): 288-291. 1983.
  •  96
    Human agency: language, duty, and value: philosophical essays in honor of J.O. Urmson (edited book)
    with J. O. Urmson, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and C. C. W. Taylor
    Stanford University Press. 1988.
    The essays in this volume explore current work in central areas of philosophy, work unified by attention to salient questions of human action and human agency. They ask what it is for humans to act knowledgeably, to use language, to be friends, to act heroically, to be mortally fortunate, and to produce as well as to appreciate art. The volume is dedicated to J. O. Urmson, in recognition of his inspirational contributions to these areas. All the essays but one have been specially written for thi…Read more
  •  9
    Human agency: language, duty, and value: philosophical essays in honor of J.O. Urmson (edited book, review)
    with J. O. Urmson, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and C. C. W. Taylor
    Stanford University Press. 1988.
    The essays in this volume explore current work in central areas of philosophy, work unified by attention to salient questions of human action and human agency. They ask what it is for humans to act knowledgeably, to use language, to be friends, to act heroically, to be mortally fortunate, and to produce as well as to appreciate art. The volume is dedicated to J. O. Urmson, in recognition of his inspirational contributions to these areas. All the essays but one have been specially written for thi…Read more
  •  38
    Intention and Permissibility
    with T. M. Scanlon
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 301-338. 2000.
    It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does not justify an exception to the prohibition against killing or the requ…Read more
  •  27
    Intention and Permissibility
    with T. M. Scanlon
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 74 301-338. 2000.
    [T. M. Scanlon] It is clearly impermissible to kill one person because his organs can be used to save five others who are in need of transplants. It has seemed to many that the explanation for this lies in the fact that in such cases we would be intending the death of the person whom we killed, or failed to save. What makes these actions impermissible, however, is not the agent's intention but rather the fact that the benefit envisaged does not justify an exception to the prohibition against kil…Read more
  •  87
    Wiggins and Ross
    Utilitas 10 (3): 281-285. 1998.
    Ross's attempt to undermine the consequentialist understanding of the relation between duties and outcomes might give him greater defence against the danger that outcome-related duties will come to constitute a norm, to the disadvantage of all others
  •  27
    Reading Parfit
    Erkenntnis 49 (2): 237-242. 1998.
  •  126
    On how to be a moral rationalist
    Philosophical Books 47 (2): 103-110. 2006.
  •  108
    Mill's Puzzling Footnote
    Utilitas 12 (2): 219. 2000.
    This paper discusses various possible interpretations of a complex footnote in Mill's Utilitarianism
  •  270
    In Defense of Thick Concepts
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 20 (1): 263-279. 1995.
  •  43
    Caring about Justice
    Philosophy 67 (262). 1992.
    In the post-Gilligan debate about the differences, if any, between the ways in which people of different genders see the moral world in which they live, I detect two assumptions. These can be found in Gilligan's early work, and have infected the thought of others. The first, perhaps surprisingly, is Kohlberg's Kantian account of one moral perspective, the one more easily or more naturally operated by men and which has come to be called the justice perspective. This is the perspective whose claim…Read more
  •  101
    Defending Particularism
    Metaphilosophy 30 (1&2): 25-32. 1999.
    In this brief response I argue that Sinnott‐Armstrong has underestimated the complexities that moral principles will have to circumvent if they are to survive particularist criticism. I also argue that we cannot yet accept Gert's accounts of moral relevance and of how a sound moral rule can survive exceptions.
  •  150
  •  38
    Book Review:The Conception of Value. Paul Grice (review)
    Ethics 104 (1): 161-. 1993.
  •  299
    Why There Is Really No Such Thing as the Theory of Motivation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 95 (1): 1-18. 1995.
    To the extent, then, that we set our face against admitting the truth of Humeanism in the theory of motivation, to that extent we are probably going to feel that there is no such thing as the theory of motivation, so conceived, at all. And that will be the position that this paper is trying to defend, though not only for this reason. It might seem miraculous that so much can be extracted from the little distinction with which we started, between the reasons why an action was right and the agent'…Read more
  • W. L. Harper, R. Stalmaker and G. Pearce , "Ifs"
    Philosophical Quarterly 33 (130): 96. 1983.
  •  87
    When reasons don’t rhyme
    The Philosophers' Magazine 37 (37): 19-24. 2007.
  •  13
    What Do Reasons Do?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 95-113. 2003.
  •  10
    What Do Reasons Do?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 95-113. 2003.
  •  222
    What Do Reasons Do?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 95-113. 2003.
  •  54
    What do reasons do?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 95-113. 2003.
  •  78
    Two Ways of Explaining Actions
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55 25-42. 2004.
    In my Practical Reality I argued that the reasons for which we act are not to be conceived of as psychological states of ourselves, but as real states of the world. The main reason for saying this was that only thus can we make sense of the idea that it is possible to act for a good reason. The good reasons we have for doing this action rather than that one consist mainly of features of the situations in which we find ourselves; they do not consist in our believing certain things about those sit…Read more
  •  129
    In my Practical Reality I argued that the reasons for which we act are not to be conceived of as psychological states of ourselves, but as real states of the world. The main reason for saying this was that only thus can we make sense of the idea that it is possible to act for a good reason. The good reasons we have for doing this action rather than that one consist mainly of features of the situations in which we find ourselves; they do not consist in our believing certain things about those sit…Read more