•  83
  •  5
    Editorials: Only Connect
    Philosophy 64 (n/a): 433. 1989.
  •  121
    Indirect perception and sense data
    Philosophical Quarterly 31 (October): 330-342. 1981.
  •  89
    Reply to Geach
    Analysis 42 (1). 1982.
  •  264
    An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind
    Cambridge University Press. 2000.
    In this book Jonathan Lowe offers a lucid and wide-ranging introduction to the philosophy of mind. Using a problem-centred approach designed to stimulate as well as instruct, he begins with a general examination of the mind-body problem and moves on to detailed examination of more specific philosophical issues concerning sensation, perception, thought and language, rationality, artificial intelligence, action, personal identity and self-knowledge. His discussion is notably broad in scope, and di…Read more
  •  51
  •  26
    Vagueness and Metaphysics
    In Giuseppina Ronzitti (ed.), Vagueness: A Guide, Springer Verlag. pp. 19--53. 2011.
  •  164
    Locke on Human Understanding, is a comprehensive introduction to John Locke's major work, Essay Concerning Human Understanding . Locke's Essay remains a key work in many philosophical fields, notably in epistemology, metaphysics and the philosophies of mind and language. In addition, Locke is often referred to as the first English empiricist. Knowledge of this influential work and figure is essential to Enlightenment thought. E. J. Lowe's approach enables students to effectively study the Essay …Read more
  •  58
    An analysis of intentionality
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (October): 294-304. 1980.
  •  229
    Categorial predication
    Ratio 25 (4): 369-386. 2012.
    When, for example, we say of something that it ‘is an object’, or ‘is an event’, or ‘is a property’, we are engaging in categorial predication: we are assigning something to a certain ontological category. Ontological categorization is clearly a type of classification, but it differs radically from the types of classification that are involved in the taxonomic practices of empirical sciences, as when a physicist says of a certain particle that it ‘is an electron’, or when a zoologist says of a c…Read more
  •  74
    Powerful Particulars: Review Essay on John Heil’s From an Ontological Point of View (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2): 466--479. 2006.
    John Heil’s new book is remarkable in many ways. In a concise, lucid and accessible manner, it develops a complete system of ontology with many strikingly original features and then applies that ontology to fundamental issues in the philosophy of mind, with illuminating results. Although Heil acknowledges his intellectual debts to C. B. Martin, he is unduly modest about his own contribution to the development and application of this novel metaphysical system. A full examination of the position t…Read more
  •  710
    The rationality of metaphysics
    Synthese 178 (1): 99-109. 2011.
    In this paper, it is argued that metaphysics, conceived as an inquiry into the ultimate nature of mind-independent reality, is a rationally indispensable intellectual discipline, with the a priori science of formal ontology at its heart. It is maintained that formal ontology, properly understood, is not a mere exercise in conceptual analysis, because its primary objective is a normative one, being nothing less than the attempt to grasp adequately the essences of things, both actual and possible,…Read more
  •  237
    Ontological Dependency
    Philosophical Papers 23 (1): 31-48. 1994.
  • MELLOR, D. H. Matters of Metaphysics (review)
    Philosophy 67 (n/a): 268. 1992.
  •  16
    Substance, Identity and Time
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 (1): 61-100. 1988.
  •  11
    Consciousness and the World (review)
    Philosophy 77 (2): 283-296. 2002.
  •  130
    This theory accords to volitions the status of basic mental actions, maintaining that these are spontaneous exercises of the will--a "two-way" power which ...
  •  314
    Jonathan Lowe argues that metaphysics should be restored to a central position in philosophy, as the most fundamental form of inquiry, whose findings underpin those of all other disciplines. He portrays metaphysics as charting the possibilities of existence, by identifying the categories of being and the relations between them. He sets out his own original metaphysical system, within which he seeks to answer many of the deepest questions in philosophy. 'a very rich book... deserves to be read ca…Read more
  •  49
    'If 2 = 3, then 2 + 1 = 3 + 1': Reply to heylen and Horsten
    Philosophical Quarterly 58 (232): 528-531. 2008.
    Jan Heylen and Leon Horsten object to my proposed analysis of ordinary-language conditionals by appealing to certain putative counter-examples. In this reply, I explain how, by ignoring my reading of the indicative/subjunctive distinction, their objection misses its target. I also criticize their underlying methodology.
  •  61
    E. J. Lowe; Wright versus Lewis on the transitivity of counterfactuals, Analysis, Volume 44, Issue 4, 1 October 1984, Pages 180–183, https://doi.org/10.1093/ana.
  •  53
    Locke, Martin and substance (contributions to metaphysics)
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (201): 498--514. 2000.
  •  70
    Substance and Selfhood
    Philosophy 66 (255): 81-99. 1991.
    How could the self be a substance? There are various ways in which it could be, some familiar from the history of philosophy. I shall be rejecting these more familiar substantivalist approaches, but also the non-substantival theories traditionally opposed to them. I believe that the self is indeed a substance—in fact, that it is a simple or noncomposite substance—and, perhaps more remarkably still, that selves are, in a sense, self-creating substances. Of course, if one thinks of the notion of s…Read more