•  52
    Hume’s better argument for motivational skepticism
    Philosophical Explorations 21 (1): 76-89. 2018.
    On a standard interpretation, Hume argued that reason is not practical, because its operations are limited to “demonstration” and “probability.” But recent critics claim that by limiting reason’s operations to only these two, his argument begs the question. Despite this, a better argument for motivational skepticism can be found in Hume’s text, one that emphasizes reason’s inability to generate motive force against contrary desires or passions. Nothing can oppose an impulse but a contrary impuls…Read more
  •  156
    Late modern philosophy: essential readings with commentary (edited book)
    with Elizabeth Schmidt Radcliffe, Fritz Allhoff, and Anand Vaidya
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2007.
    Part of the Blackwell Readings in the History of Philosophy series, this survey of late modern philosophy focuses on the key texts and philosophers of the period whose beliefs changed the course of western thought.
  •  26
    Kant and Political Philosophy (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (2): 392-393. 1994.
    Kantian political philosophy is a rich mine, and one which is hardly played out after two centuries. This substantial collection of essays validates both of those claims. Although Kant's moral philosophy has understandably received the lion's share of attention from contemporary philosophers, Beiner and Booth, both political scientists, have gathered essays which nicely illuminate the historical and political facets of Kantian practical philosophy. Anyone interested in Kantian ethics would benef…Read more
  •  105
    Kant’s Derivation of the Formula of Universal Law
    Dialogue 49 (1): 113-133. 2010.
    ABSTRACT: Critics have charged that there are gaps in the logic of Kant’s derivation of the formula of universal law. Here I defend that derivation against these charges, partly by emphasizing a neglected teleological principle that Kant alluded to in his argument, and partly by clarifying what he meant by actions’ “conformity to universal law.” He meant that actions conform to universal law just when their maxims can belong to a unified system of principles. An analogy with objects’ conformity …Read more
  •  101
    Kant's Incorporation Requirement: Freedom and Character in the Empirical World
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (3): 425-451. 2008.
    In Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason Kant wrote that ‘freedom of the power of choice has the characteristic, entirely peculiar to it, that it cannot be determined to action through any incentive except insofar as the human being has incorporated it into his maxim.’ This is an obscure statement, in both meaning and provenance. Yet almost all recent interpreters of Kant's practical philosophy find it crucial for understanding his theories of freedom and motivation, since it seems to in…Read more
  •  121
    False Negatives of the Categorical Imperative
    Mind 124 (493): 177-200. 2015.
    The categorical imperative can be construed as a universalization test for moral permissibility. False negatives of the categorical imperative would be maxims failing this test, despite the permissibility of their actions; maxims like: ‘I’ll withdraw all my savings on April 15th’. Examples of purported false negatives familiar from the literature can be grouped into three general categories, and dispatched by applying category-specific methods for proper formulation of their maxims, or for prope…Read more
  •  168
    Maxims in Kant's practical philosophy
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (1): 65-83. 2006.
    : A standard interpretation of Kantian "maxims" sees them as expressing reasons for action, implying that we cannot act without a maxim. But recent challenges to this interpretation claim that Kant viewed acting on maxims as optional. Kant's understanding of maxims derives from Christian Wolff, who regarded maxims as major premises of the practical syllogism. This supports the standard interpretation. Yet Kant also viewed commitments to maxims as essential for virtue and character development, w…Read more
  •  183
    Kantian moral motivation and the feeling of respect
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 31 (3): 421-435. 1993.